26.09.2013 Views

Religion, Theology, and Philosophy on the Way to Being and Time ...

Religion, Theology, and Philosophy on the Way to Being and Time ...

Religion, Theology, and Philosophy on the Way to Being and Time ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Research<br />

in<br />

Phenomenology<br />

Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 www.brill.nl/rp<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>, Th eology, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Way</strong> <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>: Heidegger, <strong>the</strong> Hermeneutical, <strong>the</strong><br />

Factical, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> His<strong>to</strong>rical with Respect <strong>to</strong><br />

Dil<strong>the</strong>y <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Early Christianity<br />

István M. Fehér<br />

ELTE University Budapest<br />

Abstract<br />

My aim in <strong>the</strong> present paper is <strong>to</strong> show <strong>the</strong> signifi cance of Heidegger’s phenomenology of religi<strong>on</strong><br />

as an important step <strong>on</strong> his way <strong>to</strong> his magnum opus. First, I wish <strong>to</strong> exhibit traits characteristic<br />

of Heidegger’s path of thinking in terms of his c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> with phenomenology,<br />

his<strong>to</strong>ricism, hermeneutics, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Lebensphilosophie. I will <strong>the</strong>n argue, in a sec<strong>on</strong>d step, that it was<br />

with an eye <strong>to</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> drawing up<strong>on</strong>, his previous underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of religi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> religious life, as<br />

well as of <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong> between faith <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>ology, that Heidegger was <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceive of philosophy<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> its relati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> human existence in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>. Both <strong>the</strong>ology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> philosophy off er a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>ceptual elaborati<strong>on</strong> of something previously enacted or lived (a sort of having-been) <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, in<br />

doing so, are at <strong>the</strong> same time meant <strong>to</strong> refer back <strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reinforce what <strong>the</strong>y grow out of—faith<br />

or factical life.<br />

Keywords<br />

hermeneutics, phenomenology, factical life, faith, <strong>the</strong>ology<br />

Introducti<strong>on</strong><br />

Martin Heidegger’s thinking has had a durable <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> powerful infl uence not<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly up<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophy of <strong>the</strong> twentieth century but up<strong>on</strong> a number of<br />

disciplines within <strong>the</strong> humanities as well. One of <strong>the</strong> disciplines that Heidegger<br />

infl uenced most was undoubtedly <strong>the</strong>ology—both Catholic <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Protestant.<br />

Indeed, we have reas<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> say that this was <strong>the</strong> discipline that Heidegger’s<br />

thinking aff ected most. 1<br />

1) “Surely, <strong>the</strong>ology was <strong>the</strong> discipline,” wrote Ot<strong>to</strong> Pöggeler in <strong>the</strong> eighties, “in which <strong>the</strong><br />

© K<strong>on</strong>inklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2009 DOI: 10.1163/156916408X389659


100 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

Th e relevance of Heidegger’s thought for <strong>the</strong>ology is shown by <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

both Catholic <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Protestant thinkers have been able <strong>to</strong> fi nd dimensi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

of his thought fi tting <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir world-view <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> be adopted or drawn up<strong>on</strong><br />

in several important respects. Th ose dimensi<strong>on</strong>s have of course been diff erent,<br />

according <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>fessi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cerns <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> interests as <strong>the</strong>se have taken shape <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

come <strong>to</strong> be traditi<strong>on</strong>ally developed during <strong>the</strong> past centuries. While Protestant<br />

<strong>the</strong>ologians have tended <strong>to</strong> draw up<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> early Heidegger’s analysis of human<br />

existence <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, in turning <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> later Heidegger, were fascinated by <strong>the</strong> philosopher<br />

of <strong>the</strong> language-event, Catholic <strong>the</strong>ologians or <strong>the</strong>ologically interested<br />

Catholic philosophers have primarily been attracted by Heidegger’s<br />

coupling of <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical approach with <strong>the</strong> transcendental-philosophical<br />

method <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his incessant pursual of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Being</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>. 2<br />

It is important <strong>to</strong> realize however that <strong>the</strong>re is a reciprocal infl uence operating<br />

here: <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> of how Heidegger’s thought—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> from time <strong>to</strong> time<br />

exactly which dimensi<strong>on</strong>(s) of it—infl uenced <strong>the</strong>ology should be integrated<br />

by <strong>the</strong> reverse issue c<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> decisive import of <strong>the</strong>ology for Heidegger’s<br />

philosophical beginnings <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his whole path of thinking. Th e latter point was<br />

openly acknowledged by Heidegger himself later in <strong>the</strong> fi fties in a dialogue<br />

of Unterwegs zur Sprache. In a retrospect remark he stated here quite clearly<br />

that without his <strong>the</strong>ological origins he would never have come <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> path of<br />

thought, that is, philosophy, 3 a remark which we see cropping up already in <strong>the</strong><br />

impulses coming from Heidegger proved <strong>to</strong> have <strong>the</strong> most decisive eff ects” (Ot<strong>to</strong> Pöggeler,<br />

Heidegger und die hermeneutische Philosophie [Freiburg: Alber, 1983], 414).<br />

2) See Richard Schaeffl er, Frömmigkeit des Denkens? Martin Heidegger und die katholische Th eologie<br />

(Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1978), X; Alfred Jäger, Gott. Nochmals<br />

Martin Heidegger (Tübingen: Mohr, 1978), 84. See also John D. Capu<strong>to</strong>, Heidegger <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Aquinas.<br />

An Essay <strong>on</strong> Overcoming Metaphysics (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982), 95: “Rahner,<br />

Lotz, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Coreth have all attempted <strong>to</strong> develop a transcendental Th omism which goes back not<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly <strong>to</strong> Kant but specifi cally <strong>to</strong> <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>. . . . Th ey have tried <strong>to</strong> root St. Th omas’ noti<strong>on</strong> of<br />

esse in an inherent dynamism of <strong>the</strong> intellect.” Capu<strong>to</strong> called <strong>to</strong> mind that “[i]n a brief but quite<br />

illuminating study of Heidegger’s ‘existential philosophy’, written in 1940, Karl Rahner argues,<br />

in keeping with Heidegger, for <strong>the</strong> importance of taking up <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>Being</strong> from a transcendental<br />

st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>point,” <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong> being that “an access <strong>to</strong> <strong>Being</strong> through <strong>the</strong> human subject<br />

must fi rst be established.” See fur<strong>the</strong>r Capu<strong>to</strong>, “Heidegger <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Th eology,” in Th e Cambridge<br />

Compani<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> Heidegger, ed. Charles Guign<strong>on</strong> (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993),<br />

274, 279f., 284.<br />

3) Unterwegs zur Sprache, 7th ed. (Pfullingen: Neske, 1982), 96; hereafter cited as US. (Heidegger’s<br />

works will be cited with abbreviati<strong>on</strong>s. Th e Gesamtausgabe volumes will be cited as GA followed<br />

by volume <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> page numbers; titles of GA volumes are appended. O<strong>the</strong>r works will be cited with<br />

full bibliographical data at <strong>the</strong>ir fi rst occurrence, <strong>the</strong>n with abbreviati<strong>on</strong>s. If <strong>the</strong>re are references<br />

<strong>to</strong> both <strong>the</strong> original German text <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>ding English translati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong> German pagina-


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 101<br />

sec<strong>on</strong>d part of <strong>the</strong> thirties in a recently published au<strong>to</strong>biographical passage<br />

(GA 66: 415). But even earlier, in a letter <strong>to</strong> Karl Löwith <strong>on</strong> August 19, 1921,<br />

Heidegger made reference <strong>to</strong> his “intellectual <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> wholly factic origin” in<br />

terms of being a “Christian <strong>the</strong>ologian.” 4 His <strong>the</strong>ological origins might <strong>the</strong>n be,<br />

<strong>on</strong> a fi rst approach, <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong> for (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> cause of) Heidegger’s subsequent<br />

impact <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>ology.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> above-menti<strong>on</strong>ed dialogue, Heidegger made a fur<strong>the</strong>r point that is<br />

equally important for <strong>the</strong> purposes of <strong>the</strong> present paper. He menti<strong>on</strong>ed that<br />

it was also in <strong>the</strong> course of his early <strong>the</strong>ological studies that he fi rst came<br />

across <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> grew familiar with <strong>the</strong> term “hermeneutics”—a term he found<br />

somewhat later in Dil<strong>the</strong>y <strong>to</strong>o, who, in like manner as he himself did, derived<br />

it from his own <strong>the</strong>ological studies, especially out of his c<strong>on</strong>cern with <strong>the</strong> work<br />

of Schleiermacher. 5<br />

Heidegger’s <strong>the</strong>ological origins are <strong>the</strong>n relevant not <strong>on</strong>ly for his becoming<br />

a philosopher in general but also, more especially, for <strong>the</strong> specifi c kind of hermeneutical<br />

attitude he was <strong>to</strong> adopt in philosophy <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> develop in detail.<br />

Seen in <strong>the</strong> perspective suggested by <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>fessi<strong>on</strong>ally specifi ed Christian<br />

<strong>the</strong>ological infl uences, <strong>the</strong> provisi<strong>on</strong>al end point of his youthful itinerary, <strong>Being</strong><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>, might even be claimed <strong>to</strong> attempt <strong>to</strong> bring <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> Catholic <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>the</strong> Protestant traditi<strong>on</strong>s—<strong>the</strong> former suggesting <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical perspective<br />

characteristic of neo-Scholasticism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> dating back <strong>to</strong> Heidegger’s early reading<br />

of Brentano’s dissertati<strong>on</strong> V<strong>on</strong> der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seienden<br />

nach Aris<strong>to</strong>teles as well as of Carl Braig’s Vom Sein: Abriß der On<strong>to</strong>logie, while<br />

<strong>the</strong> latter, extremely critical of Scholasticism, shifts <strong>the</strong> focus from an <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical<br />

perspective up<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> divine order <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> harm<strong>on</strong>y of <strong>the</strong> world <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

individual believer’s living or enacting his/her faith, <strong>the</strong>reby drawing heavily <strong>on</strong><br />

Lu<strong>the</strong>r’s critique of Aris<strong>to</strong>tle <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> taking up motives in St. Paul, Augustine,<br />

Pascal, Schleiermacher, Kierkegaard, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Dil<strong>the</strong>y. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> explicit program<br />

of <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>, <strong>the</strong> elaborati<strong>on</strong> of a fundamental <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logy in terms of an<br />

ti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> English paginati<strong>on</strong> are separated by a slash, <strong>the</strong> number before <strong>the</strong> slash indicating<br />

<strong>the</strong> German editi<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e after <strong>the</strong> slash <strong>the</strong> English editi<strong>on</strong>. O<strong>the</strong>r abbreviati<strong>on</strong>s: WS =<br />

Wintersemester; SS = Sommersemester.)<br />

4) See “Drei Briefe Martin Heideggers an Karl Löwith,” ed. Hartmut Tietjen, in Im Gespräch der<br />

Zeit, vol. 2 of Zur philosophischen Aktualität Heideggers, ed. Dietrich Papenfuss <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Ot<strong>to</strong> Pöggeler<br />

(Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann 1990), 29.<br />

5) As it turns out, Heidegger was registered as participant of a course of Gottfried Hoberg <strong>on</strong><br />

“Hermeneutik mit Geschichte der Exegese” during <strong>the</strong> summer semester 1910; see Heidegger-<br />

Jahrbuch, vol. 1, Heidegger und die Anfänge seines Denkens, ed. Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth<br />

G<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>er, Holger Zaborowski (Freiburg: Alber, 2004), 14.


102 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

existential analytic of <strong>the</strong> human being in an eff ort <strong>to</strong> retrieve <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> work out<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Being</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> may even be c<strong>on</strong>strued as making an attempt <strong>to</strong> unite <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

forge both traditi<strong>on</strong>s. Roughly, fundamental <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logy as <strong>the</strong> discipline destined<br />

<strong>to</strong> elaborate <strong>the</strong> <strong>Being</strong>-questi<strong>on</strong> may be seen <strong>to</strong> be of Catholic origin,<br />

whereas <strong>the</strong> existential analytic, as a c<strong>on</strong>tinuati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong><br />

early hermeneutics of facticity, may be traced back <strong>to</strong> (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> seen <strong>to</strong> take up <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

radicalize in a specifi cally formalized <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> de-<strong>the</strong>ologized manner) <strong>the</strong> Lu<strong>the</strong>r-<br />

Kierkegaardian sort of Protestant traditi<strong>on</strong> centering around subjectivity <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>the</strong> believer’s existential enactment of faith.<br />

My aim, in <strong>the</strong> present paper, is <strong>to</strong> show <strong>the</strong> signifi cance of Heidegger’s<br />

phenomenology of religi<strong>on</strong> as an important step <strong>on</strong> his way <strong>to</strong> his magnum<br />

opus. In particular, I wish <strong>to</strong> exhibit traits characteristic of, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that prove<br />

decisive for, Heidegger’s path of thinking in terms of his c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> with<br />

<strong>the</strong> leading philosophical tendencies of <strong>the</strong> age, <strong>the</strong>reby centering discussi<strong>on</strong><br />

around <strong>the</strong> reciprocal c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s of phenomenology, his<strong>to</strong>ricism, hermeneutics,<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Lebensphilosophie. Specifi cally, I will argue that it was with an eye <strong>to</strong>,<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> drawing up<strong>on</strong>, his previous underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of religi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> religious life, as<br />

well as of <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong> between faith <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>ology, that Heidegger was <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceive<br />

of philosophy <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> its relati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> human existence in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>.<br />

I will elaborate my argument in two steps. First, I will sketch an outline of<br />

Heidegger’s development in <strong>the</strong> postwar years; sec<strong>on</strong>d, against <strong>the</strong> background<br />

of this sketch I will focus more specifi cally <strong>on</strong> his 1920/21 course <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> Phenomenology<br />

of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> by selecting <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> highlighting some of <strong>the</strong> features I<br />

think are salient for Heidegger’s thinking no less than for <strong>the</strong> Sache selbst.<br />

I. Heidegger’s Philosophical Development After World War I<br />

It was due <strong>to</strong> a radical reorientati<strong>on</strong>—a veritable turn, as it were—going <strong>on</strong> in<br />

Heidegger’s thinking right after World War I that he was <strong>to</strong> fi nd his own voice<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> start <strong>the</strong> gradual move <strong>to</strong>ward <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>. Educated <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> brought up<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Scholastic traditi<strong>on</strong> but extremely resp<strong>on</strong>sive <strong>to</strong> new logical-epistemological<br />

ways of philosophizing, Heidegger started out as a talented young student<br />

committed in his academic writings fi rst <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> foremost <strong>to</strong> mainstream<br />

anti-psychologism characteristic of c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophy as represented<br />

by neo-Kantianism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> phenomenology. Th e philosophical perspective of<br />

anti-psychologism rested mainly <strong>on</strong> purely logical grounds; it was however,<br />

although perhaps indirectly, in full harm<strong>on</strong>y with <strong>the</strong> Scholastic defense of<br />

<strong>the</strong> objectivity of truth <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>reby with <strong>the</strong> apologetic tendency of anti-


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 103<br />

modernist Catholic thinking. Heidegger’s critique of psychologism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his<br />

unc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>al early adherence <strong>to</strong> anti-psychologism in general can, in this<br />

perspective, be seen <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>vey a sense of apologetic interest <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> eff ort. 6<br />

Although it is plausible <strong>to</strong> speak about quite a few pro<strong>to</strong>-hermeneutic motifs<br />

in Heidegger’s early academic writings as well as about various anticipa<strong>to</strong>ry<br />

signs of what was <strong>to</strong> come (e.g., Heidegger’s appreciati<strong>on</strong> of Duns Scotus’<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cept of haecceitas as c<strong>on</strong>veying a sense of “proximity <strong>to</strong> real life” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> being<br />

a “primal determinati<strong>on</strong> of living reality” in his habilitati<strong>on</strong> work 7 clearly<br />

suggests a growing sense for individuality, leading all <strong>the</strong> way, through <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>matizati<strong>on</strong> of factical life <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with it, of <strong>the</strong> phenomen<strong>on</strong> called<br />

Selbstwelt in <strong>the</strong> postwar years, up <strong>to</strong> Dasein’s Jemeinigkeit in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>),<br />

<strong>the</strong> prevailing atmosphere that permeates those writings remains n<strong>on</strong>e<strong>the</strong>less<br />

a Plat<strong>on</strong>izing-wissenschafts<strong>the</strong>oretisch <strong>on</strong>e.<br />

Th is outlook fades away so<strong>on</strong> after <strong>the</strong> war <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> gives way <strong>to</strong> a radical<br />

reorientati<strong>on</strong>. Ra<strong>the</strong>r than c<strong>on</strong>tinue working comfortably in <strong>the</strong> fl ow of some<br />

of <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophical tendencies as a devoted follower—relying<br />

with c<strong>on</strong>fi dence <strong>on</strong> its presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> striving, at best, <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tribute<br />

<strong>to</strong> its fur<strong>the</strong>r advancement—Heidegger embarks up<strong>on</strong> a radical undertaking<br />

of reexamining <strong>the</strong> roots of those tendencies. Th ereby he sets out <strong>on</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> so<strong>on</strong><br />

becomes indeed lifel<strong>on</strong>g engaged in, an overall c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> with <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

Western philosophical traditi<strong>on</strong>. Th is move marks <strong>the</strong> point of his becoming<br />

an aut<strong>on</strong>omous thinker: Heidegger ceases <strong>to</strong> be dependent <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> prior (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>,<br />

by necessity, naive) acceptance of any philosophical positi<strong>on</strong> whatsoever.<br />

Instead, his eff orts are directed <strong>to</strong> inquire in<strong>to</strong> as well as <strong>to</strong> reappropriate <strong>the</strong><br />

fundamental presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s underlying <strong>the</strong> most varied <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> even c<strong>on</strong>trasting<br />

philosophical positi<strong>on</strong>s. Th is operati<strong>on</strong> is given <strong>the</strong> name of destructi<strong>on</strong>; it<br />

means “a critical process in which <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cepts, which at fi rst must<br />

necessarily be employed, are dec<strong>on</strong>structed down <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> sources from which<br />

6) See Holger Zaborowski, “ ‘Herkunft aber bleibt stets Zukunft.’ Anmerkungen zur religiösen<br />

und <strong>the</strong>ologischen Dimensi<strong>on</strong> des Denkweges Martin Heideggers bis 1919,” in Heidegger-<br />

Jahrbuch, vol. 1, 149.<br />

7) GA 1: 203, 253. Dil<strong>the</strong>y was <strong>to</strong> exercise a l<strong>on</strong>g-lasting infl unce <strong>on</strong> Heidegger’s thinking. His<br />

turn <strong>to</strong> “life” can be unders<strong>to</strong>od as a turn <strong>to</strong> “facticity” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> individuality; for an interesting<br />

occurrence of <strong>the</strong> term haecceitas, used pretty much in <strong>the</strong> later Heideggerian sense of facticity<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Dasein, see Wilhelm Dil<strong>the</strong>y, Grundlegung der Wissenschaften vom Menschen, der Gesellschaft<br />

und der Geschichte, vol. 19 of Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Hans Johach, Frithjof Rodi (Göttingen:<br />

V<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>enhoeck & Ruprecht, 1982), 348: “In der Struktur des Lebens äußert sich eine individuelle<br />

Tatsächlichkeit, eine haecceitas, welche vom Verst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>e nicht als notwendig aufgezeigt werden<br />

kann.”


104 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

<strong>the</strong>y were drawn.” It is “a de-c<strong>on</strong>structing of traditi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cepts carried out<br />

in a his<strong>to</strong>rical recursi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong> . . . not a negati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong> or<br />

a c<strong>on</strong>demnati<strong>on</strong> of it as worthless; quite <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>trary, it signifi es precisely a<br />

positive appropriati<strong>on</strong> of traditi<strong>on</strong>.” 8<br />

It was with <strong>the</strong> help of <strong>the</strong> strategy of destructi<strong>on</strong> that Heidegger turned<br />

<strong>to</strong> reexamine, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> did indeed re-appropriate, <strong>the</strong> philosophical trend he felt<br />

most close <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> committed <strong>to</strong> from <strong>the</strong> very beginning, that is, Husserlian<br />

phenomenology. In a sense it might be said that <strong>the</strong> strategy of destructi<strong>on</strong><br />

itself derived from, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> was a radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of, phenomenology’s innermost<br />

claim: Back <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> things <strong>the</strong>mselves!—a weap<strong>on</strong>, as it were, grown out of, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

immediately turned against, its producer. It turned out <strong>to</strong> be a <strong>to</strong>ol with which<br />

Heidegger turned phenomenology against itself—by showing, for example,<br />

characters in it that proved <strong>to</strong> be “unphenomenological”—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> eventually performed<br />

its hermeneutical transformati<strong>on</strong>. Given <strong>the</strong> importance of this point,<br />

it will be of use <strong>to</strong> develop it in some detail.<br />

Th e Hermeneutical Transformati<strong>on</strong> of Phenomenology: A Reciprocal<br />

Radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of Phenomenology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Life-<str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

Heidegger’s appropriati<strong>on</strong> of Husserl’s phenomenology was far from being a<br />

neutral assimilati<strong>on</strong>; ra<strong>the</strong>r, it showed from <strong>the</strong> very beginning a highly critical<br />

attitude prompted by <strong>the</strong> simultaneous assimilati<strong>on</strong> of some leading motifs<br />

of life-philosophy. Appropriati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> transformati<strong>on</strong> were apparently going<br />

<strong>on</strong> h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> in h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>—which is a good example of Heidegger’s own <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

<strong>the</strong> forestructure of underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>. Seeking <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>t<br />

<strong>the</strong> leading philosophical movements, Heidegger’s strategy strived <strong>to</strong> uncover<br />

what he perceived <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>on</strong> defi ciencies inherent in <strong>the</strong> philosophical<br />

positi<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> day—positi<strong>on</strong>s that often s<strong>to</strong>od in sharpest oppositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong><br />

each o<strong>the</strong>r. Epistemologically oriented scientifi c philosophy is criticized for<br />

not being scientifi c enough; life-philosophy is accused of failing <strong>to</strong> grasp life<br />

itself; existential philosophy is charged with not seizing up<strong>on</strong> existence; his<strong>to</strong>ricism<br />

is called <strong>to</strong> account for losing sight of his<strong>to</strong>ry; <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> last but not least,<br />

phenomenology is accused of not being phenomenological enough—indeed,<br />

of being “unphenomenological.” Heidegger’s devastating critique of c<strong>on</strong>temporary<br />

trends of philosophizing employed <strong>the</strong>reby <strong>the</strong> strategy of taking <strong>the</strong>m<br />

seriously, taking <strong>the</strong>m at <strong>the</strong>ir word, as it were, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>n uncovering <strong>the</strong> extent<br />

<strong>to</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y can be shown <strong>to</strong> fail <strong>to</strong> do justice <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own claims. In <strong>the</strong><br />

discussi<strong>on</strong> that follows, I will focus <strong>on</strong> phenomenology.<br />

8) GA 24: 31/23. See also e.g. GA 59: 35, 180ff .; GA 17: 117ff .


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 105<br />

While Heidegger’s remarks <strong>on</strong> phenomenology in his academic writings<br />

scarcely amount <strong>to</strong> more than a faithful recapitulati<strong>on</strong>, expositi<strong>on</strong>, or adherence<br />

<strong>to</strong> its basic tenets, <strong>the</strong> postwar observati<strong>on</strong>s display a tendency <strong>to</strong>ward<br />

a comprehensive c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> of its basic c<strong>on</strong>cepts <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>oretical fundaments.<br />

WS 1919/20, bearing <strong>the</strong> title Th e Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology,<br />

begins with <strong>the</strong> following characteristic statement: “For phenomenology,<br />

<strong>the</strong> fundamental problem of phenomenology—its most acute problem, a problem<br />

that can never be extinguished, its most original <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> decisive problem—is<br />

phenomenology itself.” 9 Phenomenology should, for Heidegger, not just occasi<strong>on</strong>ally<br />

be c<strong>on</strong>cerned with itself. On <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>trary: if it is <strong>to</strong> be radical enough,<br />

it should bring <strong>to</strong> bear its criticism also up<strong>on</strong> itself—indeed, primarily against<br />

itself (see GA 58: 6, 145, 237).<br />

Heideggger heartily welcomed <strong>the</strong> innermost eff ort of phenomenology, <strong>the</strong><br />

proclamati<strong>on</strong> of returning <strong>to</strong> “<strong>the</strong> things <strong>the</strong>mselves” as well as what it implied:<br />

<strong>the</strong> suspending of traditi<strong>on</strong>al philosophical strategies, <strong>the</strong> dismissal of <strong>the</strong><br />

authorities, <strong>the</strong> preference of descripti<strong>on</strong> over c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>, in short: <strong>the</strong> eff ort<br />

<strong>to</strong> bring out <strong>the</strong> phenomena by going back <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> original sources of intuiti<strong>on</strong><br />

c<strong>on</strong>ceived of in terms of <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly legitimizing instance for philosophical statements<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>ories. Indeed, phenomenology, thus c<strong>on</strong>ceived, became for<br />

Heidegger identical with philosophy. From <strong>the</strong> earliest postwar period up <strong>to</strong><br />

his latest years he repeatedly maintained that phenomenology was not just a<br />

philosophical “trend,” <strong>on</strong>e “st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>point” am<strong>on</strong>g many possible o<strong>the</strong>rs, but was<br />

equivalent with <strong>the</strong> innermost possibility of philosophy itself. 10 It is important<br />

<strong>to</strong> see that phenomenology, for Heidegger, was a possibility ra<strong>the</strong>r than an<br />

actuality, that he <strong>the</strong>reby sharply distinguished between phenomenology as a<br />

way of doing philosophical research <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> phenomenology as this particular<br />

research became c<strong>on</strong>cretized in <strong>the</strong> form Husserl gave it in his work. Th is is<br />

<strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong>s why he claimed in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>: “Higher than actuality<br />

st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>s possibility. We can underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> phenomenology <strong>on</strong>ly by seizing up<strong>on</strong> it as<br />

a possibility.” 11<br />

9) GA 58: 1. See also GA 9: 36.<br />

10) See GA 56/57: 110; GA 61: 187; GA 63: 72; “Phänomenologische Interpretati<strong>on</strong>en zu Aris<strong>to</strong>teles<br />

(Anzeige der hermeneutischen Situati<strong>on</strong>),” ed. H.-U. Lessing, in vol. 6 of Dil<strong>the</strong>y Jahrbuch<br />

für Philosophie und Geschichte der Geisteswissenschaften, ed. F. Rodi (Göttingen: V<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>enhoeck &<br />

Ruprecht, 1989), 247 (hereafter: PIA); GA 20: 184; GA 21: 32, 279f.; SZ 38; GA 24: 3;<br />

GA 29/30: 534; US 95; Zur Sache des Denkens, 2nd ed. (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1976; hereafter:<br />

SD) 90.<br />

11) Sein und Zeit, 15th ed. (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1979), 38, hereafter SZ. Italics in original. See<br />

already in <strong>the</strong> early lecture courses, e.g., GA 63: 107; GA 17: 263.


106 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

It was precisely this character of open possibility, characteristic of <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

indeed indispensable for any kind of serious <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> aut<strong>on</strong>omous philosophical<br />

inquiry, that Heidegger found fascinating in adhering <strong>to</strong> Husserl’s phenomenology<br />

after <strong>the</strong> war. By c<strong>on</strong>trast, from <strong>the</strong> very beginning he had serious<br />

doubts <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> made critical remarks about <strong>the</strong> transcendental c<strong>on</strong>cretizati<strong>on</strong><br />

of it carried out by Husserl. KNS (= Kriegsnotsemester) 1919 shows already<br />

some important reservati<strong>on</strong>s about Husserl’s actual phenomenology (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with it <strong>the</strong> outlines of ano<strong>the</strong>r possible phenomenology). Th ese<br />

remarks are woven in<strong>to</strong> Heidegger’s criticism of epistemologically oriented<br />

neo-Kantian philosophy as such <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> appear in <strong>the</strong> form of an attack against<br />

<strong>the</strong> primacy of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical (this attack is motivated by Dil<strong>the</strong>y, lifephilosophy,<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his<strong>to</strong>ricism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> is brought <strong>to</strong> bear up<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole metaphysical-<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical<br />

traditi<strong>on</strong> going back <strong>to</strong> Aris<strong>to</strong>tle). Heidegger observes<br />

that <strong>the</strong> dis<strong>to</strong>rtive representati<strong>on</strong>s of life <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> envir<strong>on</strong>ing world are due not<br />

simply <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> prevalence of naturalism, as Husserl thinks <strong>the</strong>y are, but <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> dominati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical in general. 12 Heidegger here interprets Husserl’s<br />

“principle of all principles” <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> eff ect that it is not of a <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

character but expresses <strong>the</strong> most original attitude (Urhaltung) of life itself, that<br />

of remaining close <strong>to</strong> its own experiencing. 13 It expresses indeed a fundamental<br />

attitude (Grundhaltung) ra<strong>the</strong>r than a (scientifi c) method. To claim phenomenology<br />

was a st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>point would be a “mortal sin,” because it would<br />

restrict its possibilities. But, Heidegger immediately asks, is it not already a<br />

deviati<strong>on</strong>, of <strong>the</strong> character of a hidden <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>to</strong> turn <strong>the</strong> sphere of living<br />

experience in<strong>to</strong> something given? 14 Th is doubt is <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> very fi rst signs<br />

of Heidegger’s fundamental dissatisfacti<strong>on</strong> with Husserlian phenomenology,<br />

which will lead up <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> gr<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>iose critique of 1925 in which Husserl will<br />

be charged with dogmatism (an unphenomenological attitude) regarding nothing<br />

less than <strong>the</strong> delimitati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> ownmost research fi eld of phenomenology<br />

12) GA 56/57: 87.<br />

13) GA 56/57: 109 f. On several occasi<strong>on</strong>s, Heidegger will later return <strong>to</strong> interpret Husserl’s<br />

“principle of all principles.” In retrospect, he will say in <strong>the</strong> sixties that he wanted <strong>to</strong> rethink<br />

exactly this principle <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with it, <strong>the</strong> specifi c “matter” of phenomenology itself (cf.<br />

SD 69ff .). See especially <strong>the</strong> following hints: “die Phänomenologie bewußt und entschieden in<br />

die Überlieferung der neuzeitlichen Philosophie einschwenkte.” “Die Phänomenologie behielt<br />

die ‘Bewußtseinserlebnisse’ als ihren <strong>the</strong>matischen Bereich bei” (ibid., 84).<br />

14) GA 56/57: 111. (“zu einem Gegebenen zu stempeln” = give it a stamp of something given, <strong>to</strong><br />

seal it, <strong>to</strong> reify it, as something given). See also GA 58: 221.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 107<br />

itself, i.e., transcendental c<strong>on</strong>sciousness. 15 Th e world of lived experience knows<br />

of no such duality as that between object <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> knowledge.<br />

If we leap forward <strong>to</strong> Heidegger’s most detailed critique of Husserl’s phenomenology<br />

as provided in <strong>the</strong> 1925 lecture course, we see that its central<br />

<strong>the</strong>me is, <strong>on</strong>ce again, <strong>the</strong> delimitati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> specifi c research fi eld of phenomenology<br />

itself, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> self-c<strong>on</strong>cretizati<strong>on</strong> of phenomenological<br />

philosophy out of its own initial principle or maxim. Th e basic issue is related<br />

<strong>to</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> how phenomenology gets access <strong>to</strong> (comes <strong>to</strong> delimit) its own<br />

research fi eld, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> procedure <strong>the</strong>reby employed is phenomenologically<br />

coherent or not. Over against <strong>the</strong> charges of dogmatism, as formulated<br />

by Rickert, Heidegger comes <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>, after detailed analyses, that it<br />

is not intenti<strong>on</strong>ality as such that might legitimately be claimed <strong>to</strong> be dogmatic<br />

but ra<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>to</strong> which intenti<strong>on</strong>ality gets tacitly linked, or bound, or tied,<br />

that which is built under this structure—in o<strong>the</strong>r words, that of which it is<br />

claimed <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> specifi c structure. In fact, intenti<strong>on</strong>ality is held <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong><br />

specifi c structure of <strong>the</strong> psyche, reas<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, etc. (ra<strong>the</strong>r than, say,<br />

nature), all of which are <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical regi<strong>on</strong>s that are naively, i.e., traditi<strong>on</strong>ally<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>refore dogmatically, assumed ra<strong>the</strong>r than phenomenologically discussed<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> delimited. Ra<strong>the</strong>r than an ultimate explanati<strong>on</strong> of psychic reality,<br />

Heidegger observes signifi cantly, intenti<strong>on</strong>ality is a way <strong>to</strong> overcome such traditi<strong>on</strong>al<br />

<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical realities as psyche, c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, reas<strong>on</strong>. 16<br />

Th e questi<strong>on</strong> is whe<strong>the</strong>r access <strong>to</strong> that of which intenti<strong>on</strong>ality is declared <strong>to</strong><br />

be <strong>the</strong> structure is attained in a phenomenological way. Th e issue c<strong>on</strong>cerns <strong>the</strong><br />

delimitati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> “thing itself” in a phenomenological way, <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong><br />

of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> linking of intenti<strong>on</strong>ality <strong>to</strong> pure c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, or <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> transcendental<br />

ego, is carried out phenomenologically <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> not simply by taking<br />

over <strong>the</strong> leading idea of modern Cartesian-Kantian philosophy—a doubt that<br />

proves <strong>to</strong> be well-founded. 17 Although Husserl claims <strong>to</strong> suspend, put in<strong>to</strong><br />

brackets, “asserti<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>cerning being” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>reby leaves <strong>the</strong> being of intenti<strong>on</strong>ality<br />

obscure, he never<strong>the</strong>less tacitly links it <strong>to</strong> an <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical regi<strong>on</strong> called<br />

transcendental c<strong>on</strong>sciousness. Moreover, he makes distincti<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>Being</strong> like<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e between <strong>Being</strong> as c<strong>on</strong>sciousness <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> transcendent being—which he<br />

15) See GA 20: 159, 178. For <strong>the</strong> same point in his<strong>to</strong>rical perspective going back <strong>to</strong> Descartes, see<br />

GA 17, esp. 105.<br />

16) GA 20: 62ff . “It is a questi<strong>on</strong> of underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> basis of intenti<strong>on</strong>ality,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing intenti<strong>on</strong>ality <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> basis of prec<strong>on</strong>ceived ideas about <strong>the</strong> subject”<br />

(Rudolf Bernet, “Husserl <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Heidegger <strong>on</strong> Intenti<strong>on</strong>ality <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Being</strong>,” Journal of <strong>the</strong> British Society<br />

for Phenomenology 21 [May 1990]: 143).<br />

17) See GA 20: 147.


108 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

called himself, symp<strong>to</strong>matically, “<strong>the</strong> most radical of all distincti<strong>on</strong>s of being.” 18<br />

Remarkably enough, while prohibiting making asserti<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>cerning being,<br />

phenomenology tacitly commits itself <strong>to</strong> certain <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical positi<strong>on</strong>s—i.e.,<br />

without <strong>the</strong>matizing <strong>the</strong> access <strong>to</strong> those positi<strong>on</strong>s phenomenologically. 19 Th at<br />

phenomenology may be shown <strong>to</strong> be intrinsically incoherent or inc<strong>on</strong>sistent,<br />

i.e., “unphenomenological,” 20 aff ected with metaphysical bias, is signifi cant<br />

enough. Insofar as <strong>the</strong> principle of phenomenology (“To <strong>the</strong> things <strong>the</strong>mselves!”)<br />

requires suspensi<strong>on</strong> of every unwarranted c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> subjecting <strong>the</strong><br />

unquesti<strong>on</strong>ed dominati<strong>on</strong> of philosophical <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>to</strong> critical examinati<strong>on</strong>, as<br />

well as <strong>the</strong> return <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> original sources of intuiti<strong>on</strong>, Heidegger’s objecti<strong>on</strong><br />

strikes home—it turns out <strong>to</strong> be eminently phenomenological.<br />

Th e access <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> transcendental regi<strong>on</strong> of pure c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, as erecting<br />

itself up<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> replacing <strong>the</strong> experience of empirical reality, is characterized by<br />

Husserl in terms of a change in attitude. In <strong>the</strong> natural attitude, <strong>the</strong> world<br />

is present as a spatio-temporal sequence of events, including <strong>the</strong> psychic processes<br />

going <strong>on</strong> in <strong>the</strong> minds of empirically existing people. As opposed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

new realm, i.e., <strong>the</strong> pure regi<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>sciousness that we are about <strong>to</strong> enter,<br />

humans appear here merely as living beings, zoological objects am<strong>on</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

However, Heidegger objects, we may legitimately ask: does <strong>on</strong>e really experience<br />

<strong>on</strong>eself in <strong>the</strong> manner described here in this alleged “natural attitude”? In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, is this attitude indeed so natural? Is it not ra<strong>the</strong>r artifi cial or, in<br />

any case, <strong>the</strong>oretical? Do I really experience myself “naturally” as a living being,<br />

a zoological object, out <strong>the</strong>re, present-at-h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> as any o<strong>the</strong>r? 21<br />

18) See GA 20: 155, 157f., 178. See also GA 17: 264. For Husserl’s distincti<strong>on</strong> see his Ideen zu<br />

einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. I. Buch: Allgemeine Einführung<br />

in die reine Phänomenologie, §76; Husserliana, III/1, ed. by K. Schuhmann (Th e Hague: Nijhoff ,<br />

1976), 159.<br />

19) See GA 20: 140, 157ff ., 178. Husserl’s claim c<strong>on</strong>cerning Voraussetzungslosigkeit should not be<br />

misinterpreted, Herbert Spiegelberg writes, “in <strong>the</strong> sense of a <strong>to</strong>tal rejecti<strong>on</strong> of any beliefs whatsoever,<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> of a program <strong>to</strong> start <strong>the</strong> philosophic enterprise from absolute zero.” It “st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>s for an<br />

attempt <strong>to</strong> eliminate merely presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s that have not been thoroughly examined, or, at least<br />

in principle, been presented for such examinati<strong>on</strong>. It is thus not freedom from all presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s,<br />

but merely freedom from phenomenologically unclarifi ed, unverifi ed, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> unverifi able presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

that is involved” (Herbert Spiegelberg, Th e Phenomenological Movement: A His<strong>to</strong>rical<br />

Introducti<strong>on</strong>, 3rd ed. [Th e Hague: Nijhoff , 1984], 77). It is important <strong>to</strong> see that Heidegger’s<br />

above criticism does apply <strong>to</strong> Husserl even <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> precisely in <strong>the</strong> sense in which Spiegelberg<br />

rec<strong>on</strong>structs Husserl’s claim c<strong>on</strong>cerning Voraussetzungslosigkeit.<br />

20) GA 20: 159, 178. Th e term “unphänomenologisch” crops up already in 1923 in a remark stating<br />

that it is unphenomenological <strong>to</strong> hold ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>to</strong> be an ideal of scientifi city (GA 63: 72).<br />

21) See GA 20: 131f., 155f., 162, 172; SZ 120. “Husserl tended <strong>to</strong> see man in <strong>the</strong> natural atti-


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 109<br />

Th e fl ow of Heidegger’s critical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s is, as can be seen, wholly<br />

phenomenological. It is completely in line with Husserl’s “principle of all principles”<br />

22 which suggests that what it comes down <strong>to</strong> is <strong>to</strong> proceed in an unprejudiced<br />

way, without any prior bias, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> simply accept whatever is off ered<br />

us in intuiti<strong>on</strong>. It would indeed be hard <strong>to</strong> deny that it is not as zoological<br />

objects that we primarily do experience ourselves in <strong>the</strong> world of natural<br />

attitude—that in order <strong>to</strong> experience ourselves in that way we must previously<br />

have shifted over in<strong>to</strong> an attitude of a particular <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

Th e (phenomenological) implicati<strong>on</strong>s of this most phenomenological criticism<br />

of phenomenology for a radicalizati<strong>on</strong> or transformati<strong>on</strong> of it are simple<br />

enough: an attempt should be made <strong>to</strong> experience <strong>the</strong> intenti<strong>on</strong>al being more<br />

originally, in a more unprejudiced way, in its “natural” setting, <strong>the</strong>reby no l<strong>on</strong>ger<br />

taking <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong>al defi niti<strong>on</strong> of man as “animal rati<strong>on</strong>ale” for granted.<br />

What is required is <strong>to</strong> experience <strong>the</strong> natural attitude more naturally, <strong>the</strong>reby<br />

making <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong>s empirical-transcendental, ideal-real, etc., not <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

superfl uous but indeed unphenomenological <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> empty. And, when we look<br />

at <strong>the</strong> matter more closely, this is precisely what <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong> will do with<br />

<strong>the</strong> title of existential analytic.<br />

Heidegger’s criticism of Husserlian phenomenology, his transformati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of it, thus rests <strong>on</strong> eminently phenomenological grounds; it is,<br />

it seems, as immanent a criticism as <strong>on</strong>e may ever be claimed <strong>to</strong> be. Never<strong>the</strong>less,<br />

as I c<strong>on</strong>tend, it could never have been carried out had Heidegger previously<br />

not assimilated some basic motives of life-philosophy. Th ese were indeed<br />

very much in play in his c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ting Husserlian transcendental phenomenology<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>tributed decisively <strong>to</strong> its hermeneutical transformati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

tude, e.g. <strong>the</strong> empirical ego, simply in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with psycho-physical <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> neurological processes,<br />

hence as a thing-entity of nature. In that regard, Heidegger c<strong>on</strong>sidered <strong>the</strong> ‘natural attitude’<br />

in Husserl not <strong>to</strong> be natural enough” (Th omas Sheehan. “Heidegger’s <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g> of Mind,”<br />

in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g> of Mind, vol. 4 of C<strong>on</strong>temporary <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g>: A New Survey, ed. G. Fløistad, [Th e<br />

Hague: Nijhoff , 1983], 294).<br />

22) See Ideas I, § 24: “No c<strong>on</strong>ceivable <strong>the</strong>ory can make us err with respect <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> principle of all<br />

principles: that every originary presentive intuiti<strong>on</strong> is a legitimizing source of cogniti<strong>on</strong>, that everything<br />

originally (so <strong>to</strong> speak, in its ‘pers<strong>on</strong>al’ actuality) off ered <strong>to</strong> us in ‘intuiti<strong>on</strong>’ is <strong>to</strong> be accepted<br />

simply as what it is presented as being, but also <strong>on</strong>ly within <strong>the</strong> limits in which it is presented <strong>the</strong>re”<br />

[Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie § 24, Husserliana, III/1, 51: “Am Prinzip aller<br />

Prinzipien, daß jeder originär gebende Anschauung eine Rechtsquelle der Erkenntnis sei, daß alles,<br />

was sich uns in der ‘Intutiti<strong>on</strong>’ originär (sozusagen in seiner leibhaften Wirklichkeit) darbietet,<br />

einfach hinzunehmen sei, als was es sich gibt, aber auch nur in den Schranken, in denen es sich da<br />

gibt, kann uns keine erdenkliche Th eorie irre machen.”]


110 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

Heidegger’s postwar turn may comprehensively be characterized as an overall<br />

attempt at appropriati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reappropriati<strong>on</strong>, i.e., as an eff ort <strong>to</strong> come <strong>to</strong><br />

terms with <strong>the</strong> signifi cant tendencies of c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophy—inclusive<br />

of <strong>the</strong> philosophical traditi<strong>on</strong> in general—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, more importantly, with what<br />

philosophy really is, inclusive of its subject matter, i.e., life. Whatever <strong>the</strong><br />

underlying motivati<strong>on</strong> may be that catalyzed this turn, his postwar password<br />

sounds: back <strong>to</strong> life in its originality! Th is was <strong>the</strong> way Heidegger came <strong>to</strong><br />

underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Husserl’s password <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> translated it in<strong>to</strong> his own c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality.<br />

He specifi cally did so in <strong>the</strong> lecture course 1919/20 <strong>on</strong> Th e Fundamental<br />

Problems of Phenomenology, which started with <strong>the</strong> above-cited urge for phenomenology’s<br />

self-renewal <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> self-criticism. Th e thing <strong>to</strong> which philosophy<br />

had <strong>to</strong> fi nd its way back <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> which was <strong>the</strong> origin of all meaning, was, for<br />

Heidegger, not transcendental c<strong>on</strong>sciousness but life in its originality. In <strong>the</strong><br />

course of this lecture, he kept designating life as <strong>the</strong> “primal phenomen<strong>on</strong>”<br />

(Urphänomen) 23 for phenomenology in general. Phenomenology thus c<strong>on</strong>ceived,<br />

centering around life as being both <strong>the</strong> origin <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> subject matter<br />

of philosophy, was repeatedly called pre-<strong>the</strong>oretical “primal science” or<br />

“science of <strong>the</strong> origins” (Urwissenschaft, Ursprungswissenschaft).<br />

In a sense, <strong>the</strong> tendency <strong>to</strong> gain a new access <strong>to</strong> life was widespread at <strong>the</strong><br />

time <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> refl ected <strong>the</strong> eff orts of <strong>the</strong> age, 24 so Heidegger may be seen <strong>to</strong> have<br />

just taken seriously <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> have radicalized this urge coming from thinkers<br />

such as Na<strong>to</strong>rp, Dil<strong>the</strong>y, Bergs<strong>on</strong>, Simmel, Jaspers, Scheler, James. 25 In <strong>the</strong><br />

midst of various devastating criticisms, more often than not Heidegger takes<br />

great pains <strong>to</strong> note that <strong>the</strong>re is a positive, an original impulse inherent in lifephilosophy—that<br />

he indeed does appreciate <strong>the</strong> impulse, while what he rejects<br />

is just its insuffi cient (because parasitic) realizati<strong>on</strong>. When Heidegger, for all<br />

his criticism, emphasizes <strong>the</strong> positive tendencies of life-philosophy, <strong>the</strong> philosopher<br />

he most frequently has in mind is Dil<strong>the</strong>y. 26 And we can hardly c<strong>on</strong>ceive<br />

of Heidegger’s his<strong>to</strong>ricist oppositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> Husserl’s transcendental ego, <strong>the</strong><br />

23) GA 59: 15, 18, 23, 39, 40, 176.<br />

24) Th is his<strong>to</strong>rical background is referred <strong>to</strong> by Heidegger several times in his early lectures. See<br />

GA 58: 1ff .: 25ff ., GA 59: 12f., 15 (“Die Problematik der gegenwärtigen Philosophie ist um das<br />

‘Leben’ als das ‘Urphänomen’ zentriert”) 97; GA 9: 14f. (“So ist denn die Problematik der gegenwärtigen<br />

Philosophie vorwiegend um das ‘Leben’ als das ‘Urphänomen’ zentriert”).<br />

25) See GA 58: 3,162; GA 61: 117, 174, 189; GA 63: 64, 69; GA 9: 14f.<br />

26) See, for example, GA 63: 42: “Die eigentliche Tendenz Dil<strong>the</strong>y ist nicht die, als die sie hier<br />

[sc., by Spranger] angegeben ist”), see fur<strong>the</strong>r GA 9: 13 f. (“Die Lebensphilosophie, vor allem<br />

eine solche v<strong>on</strong> der Höhenstufe Dil<strong>the</strong>ys . . . muß auf ihre positiven Tendenzen befragt werden,<br />

daraufhin, ob in ihr nicht doch . . . eine radikale Tendenz des Philosophierens vorwagt. Im Abse-


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 111<br />

stress up<strong>on</strong> “das His<strong>to</strong>rische” without Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s infl uence. 27 Heidegger suggests<br />

that <strong>the</strong> basic eff ort of life-philosophy is correct, he seems even <strong>to</strong> share <strong>the</strong><br />

view of c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophy that <strong>the</strong> object primarily <strong>to</strong> be approached<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> investigated is “life.” 28 What he objects <strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> disapproves of is that ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than developing c<strong>on</strong>ceptual means adequate <strong>to</strong> its ownmost object, i.e., “life,”<br />

life-philosophy relies up<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>ols of <strong>the</strong> adversary for its own c<strong>on</strong>cepts. 29<br />

Th at is also <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong> why, having realized that <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>ols are not equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

task, life-philosophers tend <strong>to</strong> come inevitably <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> that life, his<strong>to</strong>ry,<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> existence are irrati<strong>on</strong>al. 30 Th e point Heidegger makes could be put as<br />

hen darauf bewegt ich diese Kritik” [italics in original]); GA 61: 7; GA 17: 301, 320; GA 64: 7ff .;<br />

SZ 46f. See also Heidegger’s retrospective remark GA 66: 412.<br />

27) For Heidegger’s stress <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical see GA 9: 31, 32f., 36, 38; GA 56/57: 85, 88f., 117,<br />

206; GA 61: 1, 76, 111, 159, 163; GA 63: 83, 107; GA 60: 31ff . <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> passim. Heidegger frequently<br />

spoke of Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s appreciati<strong>on</strong> of Husserl (see, for example, GA 56/57: 165; GA 20: 30);<br />

this may have led him <strong>to</strong> think that what he was called <strong>to</strong> do was <strong>to</strong> unite <strong>the</strong> impulses of both<br />

thinkers.<br />

28) See GA 17: 112 <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> references in note 24 above. Th at philosophy has life as its subject<br />

matter appears clearly in a passage of SZ also, where Heidegger suggests that <strong>the</strong> expressi<strong>on</strong><br />

“philosophy of life” amounts <strong>to</strong> nothing more than “botany of plants”—really a ple<strong>on</strong>asm—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

that in a genuine “philosophy of life” “<strong>the</strong>re lies an unexpressed tendency <strong>to</strong>wards an underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing<br />

of Dasein,” that is, existential analytic (SZ 46/BT 72 [=<strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>, trans. John Macquarrie<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Edward Robins<strong>on</strong> (New York: Harper & Row, 1962)]; see also GA 64: 40). For an<br />

anticipati<strong>on</strong> of this see GA 9: 14f.<br />

29) See Heidegger’s use of <strong>the</strong> term “Begriff ssurrogat” (GA 9: 10).<br />

30) See GA 61: 82 (“kommt es nicht zur aneignenden Aufhebung der positiven Tendenzen der<br />

modernen Lebensphilosophie” [italics in origina]); 117 (“Damit ist eine innerhalb der Lebensphilosophie<br />

unausdrücklich lebendige Tendenz ergriff en”); GA 9: 4, 13f. (“Die Lebensphilosophie,<br />

vor allem eine solche v<strong>on</strong> der Höhenstufe Dil<strong>the</strong>ys . . . muß auf ihre positiven Tendenzen<br />

befragt werden, daraufhin, ob in ihr nicht doch, wenn auch ihr selbst verdeckt und mit traditi<strong>on</strong>ell<br />

aufgeraff ten, statt ursprünglich geschöpften Ausdrucksmitteln, eine radikale Tendenz des<br />

Philosophierens vorwagt. Im Absehen darauf bewegt ich diese Kritik” [italics in original]);<br />

GA 58: 3 (“Was heißt: ‘Leben in Begriff e fassen’ . . . ‘in Worte bringen’, wo doch die Worte als<br />

volle Ausdrücke zugeschnitten sein sollen auf unsere Umwelt, auf den Raum”); 231f. (“Es ist ein<br />

in der gegenwärtigen Philosophie viel vertretener St<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>punkt, daß das faktische Leben dem<br />

Begriff gänzlich unzugänglich sei. Aber das ist nur die Kehrseite des Rati<strong>on</strong>alismus dieser Philosophie”);<br />

GA 59: 154 (“Die Lebensphilosophie ist für uns eine notwendige Stati<strong>on</strong> auf dem<br />

Wege der Philosophie, im Gegensatz zur leer formalen Transzendentalphilosophie”); GA 60: 50<br />

(“Der Begriff des Lebens ist ein vieldeutiger und v<strong>on</strong> diesem ganz allgemeinen, formalen<br />

Gesichtspunkt aus hätte eine Kritik der heutigen Lebensphilosophie einen Sinn. Nur wenn es<br />

gelingt, diesen Begriff ursprünglich positiv zu fassen, ist eine Kritik berechtigt, in einem <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>eren<br />

Sinn aber nicht, s<strong>on</strong>st verkennt sie die eigentlichen Motive der Lebensphilosophie”); GA 63: 69<br />

(“Die Tendenz der Lebensphilosophie muß aber doch im positiven Sinne genommen werden als<br />

Durchbruch einer radikaleren Tendenz des Philosophierens, obgleich die Grundlage ungenügend


112 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

follows: irrati<strong>on</strong>alist philosophy is really <strong>to</strong>o rati<strong>on</strong>al. In claiming its objects <strong>to</strong><br />

be irrati<strong>on</strong>al, it uncritically borrows <strong>the</strong> measure or c<strong>on</strong>cept of rati<strong>on</strong>ality from<br />

<strong>the</strong> adversary ra<strong>the</strong>r than elaborating a rati<strong>on</strong>ality or c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality of its own,<br />

<strong>on</strong>e that c<strong>on</strong>forms <strong>to</strong> its object. 31<br />

Th e traditi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cept of rati<strong>on</strong>ality stems from a <strong>the</strong>oretical attitude, based<br />

in its turn <strong>on</strong> a c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of humans as rati<strong>on</strong>al beings—<strong>on</strong>e more reas<strong>on</strong><br />

why Heidegger strives <strong>to</strong> disengage himself from <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong>al view of man<br />

as a rati<strong>on</strong>al animal <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with it, from <strong>the</strong> rati<strong>on</strong>al-irrati<strong>on</strong>al distincti<strong>on</strong>,<br />

so as <strong>to</strong> explore dimensi<strong>on</strong>s of man’s being underlying <strong>the</strong>oretical comportment.<br />

Phenomenologically seen, <strong>the</strong>oretical comportment has indeed gained<br />

mastery over <strong>the</strong> entire Western philosophical traditi<strong>on</strong>. Th e dominati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

it has been undisputed even where it has been bitterly opposed. One of<br />

Heidegger’s earliest passwords sounds <strong>the</strong>refore: “Th is hegem<strong>on</strong>y of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

must be broken.” 32<br />

It is in <strong>the</strong> course of his destructive eff orts <strong>to</strong> penetrate behind <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

comportment <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality in an attempt <strong>to</strong> gain a new <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> fresh (so <strong>to</strong><br />

ist”); 108 (“Die Polemik gegen die Lebensphilosophie . . . verfehlt alles, sieht den Gegenst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

Lebens überhaupt nicht ursprünglich . . . Deshalb ist die Polemik gegen Begriff slosigkeit rein<br />

negativ” [Heidegger has Rickert in mind]).<br />

31) See, for example, GA 63: 45: “Was heißt irrati<strong>on</strong>al? Das bestimmt sich doch nur an einer<br />

Idee v<strong>on</strong> Rati<strong>on</strong>alität. Woraus erwächst deren Bestimmung?” Th is view of Heidegger’s was <strong>to</strong> be<br />

held through four decades up <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> sixties (see SD 79). For a fuller discussi<strong>on</strong> of Heidegger’s<br />

treatment of rati<strong>on</strong>alism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> irrati<strong>on</strong>alism, see my paper “Heidegger und Lukács. Eine Hundertjahresbilanz,”<br />

in Wege und Irrwege des neueren Umganges mit Heideggers Werk, ed. István M. Fehér<br />

(Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1991), 43–70.<br />

32) GA 56/57: 59 (“Diese Vorrherrschaft des Th eoretischen muß gebrochen werden”). See also<br />

ibid., 87, 89, 97. See also GA 59: 142 (“Beherrsch<strong>the</strong>it [des heutigen Lebens] durch das Th eoretische”).<br />

By centering his destructive strategy around an overall c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical,<br />

Heidegger takes up <strong>on</strong>ce again, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> gives a thorough elaborati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong>, ano<strong>the</strong>r basic<br />

impulse of c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophy, as represented primarily by Emil Lask. What Lask called<br />

<strong>the</strong> “intellectualistic prejudice” gives preference <strong>to</strong> “thinking” in gaining access <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> n<strong>on</strong>-sensible;<br />

“faith” is unders<strong>to</strong>od in a negative sense mainly owing <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellectualistic distincti<strong>on</strong><br />

between “knowledge” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> “faith.” Th e “<strong>the</strong>oretizati<strong>on</strong> of a-<strong>the</strong>oretical comportment” also fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

aff ects all those distincti<strong>on</strong>s we usually make between, for example, “<strong>the</strong>oretical <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> practical,”<br />

“logical <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> intuitive,” “<strong>the</strong>oretical <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> aes<strong>the</strong>tic,” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> “scientifi c <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> religious” knowledge<br />

(see Emil Lask, Gesammelte Schriften, 3 vols., ed. E. Herrigel [Tübingen: Mohr, 1923], 2:204f.,<br />

208; 3:235. Heidegger did not fail <strong>to</strong> acknowledge that Lask was “<strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> most powerful<br />

[stärksten] philosophical pers<strong>on</strong>alities of <strong>the</strong> time,” adding how much he owed <strong>to</strong> him (see<br />

GA 56/57: 180). See more details in my paper “Lask, Lukács, Heidegger: Th e Problem of Irrati<strong>on</strong>ality<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> Th eory of Categories,” in Martin Heidegger. Critical Assessments, ed. Chris<strong>to</strong>pher<br />

Macann (L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1992), 2:373–405.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 113<br />

speak, “unprejudiced”) access <strong>to</strong> life that <strong>the</strong> hermeneutic problematic emerges<br />

in Heidegger’s post war lecture courses. As early as in <strong>the</strong> immediate postwar<br />

years, Heidegger off ers, as alternative <strong>to</strong> rati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cepts <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>oretical knowing,<br />

what he calls “hermeneutical c<strong>on</strong>cepts,” 33 or—over against pure or <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

intuiti<strong>on</strong>—“hermeneutical intuiti<strong>on</strong>.” 34 “Hermeneutics,” “hermeneutical,”<br />

emerge as rival c<strong>on</strong>cepts <strong>to</strong> “<strong>the</strong>ory,” “<strong>the</strong>oretical,” unders<strong>to</strong>od in terms of<br />

“<strong>the</strong>oretically neutral.” 35 Th e descripti<strong>on</strong> of life, or “facticity,” becomes hermeneutical,<br />

obtains an overall hermeneutic character, precisely in virtue of <strong>the</strong><br />

realizati<strong>on</strong> that interpretati<strong>on</strong> cannot be regarded as something added, as a<br />

kind of extensi<strong>on</strong> or annex, as it were, <strong>to</strong> some <strong>the</strong>oretically neutral (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, as<br />

such, allegedly “objective”) descripti<strong>on</strong> of a state of aff airs: ra<strong>the</strong>r, preliminary<br />

“interpretedness” is inherent in all kinds of descripti<strong>on</strong>, in all kinds of seeing,<br />

saying, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> experiencing. 36 If <strong>the</strong>re is no “pure” <strong>the</strong>ory (for “<strong>the</strong>ory” is a derivative<br />

mode of being or comportment of <strong>on</strong>e particular being called human),<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no pure descripti<strong>on</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r. What this insight implies for an adequate<br />

descripti<strong>on</strong> of life or facticity is that <strong>the</strong>oretical c<strong>on</strong>cepts, as well as <strong>the</strong> language<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ory speaks, should be ab<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>ed in favor of a language growing<br />

out of everyday life <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> able <strong>to</strong> let things be seen in <strong>the</strong>ir interpretedness, that<br />

is, exactly <strong>the</strong> way we encounter <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> have <strong>to</strong> do with <strong>the</strong>m (a hammer, for<br />

example, is primarily encountered as a <strong>to</strong>ol for hitting nails in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> wall ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than as a neutral thing out <strong>the</strong>re having <strong>the</strong> property of weight). Th eoretically<br />

(<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> ahis<strong>to</strong>rically) neutral knowledge is opposed <strong>to</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> gives way <strong>to</strong>, existentially<br />

(<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his<strong>to</strong>rically) involved underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing (or pre-underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing) <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

interpreting—whereby knowledge becomes at best a subdivisi<strong>on</strong> of underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing.<br />

37 All <strong>the</strong>se eff orts are in <strong>the</strong> service of seizing up<strong>on</strong> “life.” Th e main character<br />

of <strong>the</strong> latter is claimed <strong>to</strong> be c<strong>on</strong>cern (Sorge) ra<strong>the</strong>r than knowledge. 38<br />

Th e science that is destined <strong>to</strong> provide access <strong>to</strong> life in its originality is,<br />

as should be clear from what has been rec<strong>on</strong>structed, intrinsically interpretive,<br />

i.e., hermeneutical—an insight that explicitly crops up in a note of <strong>the</strong><br />

1919/20 lecture course saying: “<strong>the</strong> science of <strong>the</strong> origins is ultimately <strong>the</strong><br />

33) GA 9: 32.<br />

34) GA 56/57: 117.<br />

35) “Kategorie ist interpretierend und ist nur interpretierend, und zwar das faktische Leben, angeeignet<br />

in existenzieller Bekümmerung” (GA 61: 86f.).<br />

36) See explicitly, for example, GA 17: 294 (“Wir sehen die Welt immer in einem als”); fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

PIA 241, 264. Later GA 20: 75, 190, 416; SZ 169, 383.<br />

37) See, for example, GA 64: 32: “Das primäre Erkennen . . . ist Auslegung.” Ibid., 36: “Auslegen<br />

ist das primäre Erkennen.” See <strong>the</strong>n SZ 147.<br />

38) See GA 61: 89ff .; PIA 240.


114 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

hermeneutical science.” 39 And in Oskar Becker’s lecture note of <strong>the</strong> course<br />

SS 1919 we can read: “phenomenology, <strong>the</strong> primal science of philosophy, is<br />

an underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing science.” 40<br />

To sum up: <strong>the</strong> radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of phenomenology leads Heidegger <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>matizati<strong>on</strong> of factical life (<strong>to</strong> a kind of life phenomenology,) 41 whereas <strong>the</strong><br />

descripti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> latter, in its turn, requires a c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality of its own, a hermeneutic<br />

perspective, a dispositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> remain as close <strong>to</strong> life in its originality<br />

as possible (since <strong>the</strong>oretical comportment means having distanced <strong>on</strong>eself<br />

from genuine life, having displaced <strong>on</strong>eself in<strong>to</strong> a derivative attitude). Th is<br />

proximity <strong>to</strong> genuine life, as well as <strong>the</strong> willingness <strong>to</strong> accompany it, <strong>to</strong> come<br />

al<strong>on</strong>g with it all <strong>the</strong> way (Mitgehen), <strong>to</strong> be achieved by hermeneutic attitude<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality, is a dispositi<strong>on</strong> Heidegger symp<strong>to</strong>matically <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> semireligiously<br />

calls humilitas animi. 42<br />

39) GA 58: 55: “Ursprungswissenschaft letztlich die hermeneutische ist.”<br />

40) GA 56/57: 216.<br />

41) Heidegger was known <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reported by c<strong>on</strong>temporaries <strong>to</strong> have developed a “phenomenology<br />

of life” in his post war lecture courses; H. Tanabe, presumably <strong>the</strong> fi rst <strong>to</strong> write <strong>on</strong> Heidegger<br />

abroad, reported about his German experiences in Japan in 1924 with <strong>the</strong> title: “A New Turn<br />

in Phenomenology: Heidegger’s Phenomenology of Life” (see Ot<strong>to</strong> Pöggeler, “Neue Wege mit<br />

Heidegger?” Philosophische Rundschau 29, nos. 1/2 [1982]: 57; see also his “Zeit und Sein bei<br />

Heidegger,” in Zeit und Zeitlichkeit bei Husserl und Heidegger, vol. 14 of Phänomenologische<br />

Forschungen, ed. Ernst W. Orth [Freiburg: Alber, 1983], 155).<br />

42) GA 58: 23. For Mitgehen, see GA 58: 23, 158, 162, 185, 255, 262; for later, see GA 29/30:<br />

296ff . Th e proximity <strong>to</strong> life (Lebensnähe) was also an urge of <strong>the</strong> age which Heidegger has taken<br />

up <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reacted up<strong>on</strong>; see GA 63: 64. It may be of some importance <strong>to</strong> note that <strong>the</strong> semireligious<br />

t<strong>on</strong>e that occasi<strong>on</strong>ally permeates this lecture course may be partly due <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

precisely in that semester (WS 1919/20), Heidegger had also announced, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> been preparing <strong>to</strong><br />

deliver, a course <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophical Foundati<strong>on</strong>s of Mediaeval Mysticism. Although he had been<br />

working hard <strong>on</strong> it, due <strong>to</strong> lack of time he could not get ready with <strong>the</strong> preparati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore in<br />

a letter <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Faculty dated August 30, 1919, he asked for permissi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> cancel it <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> transform<br />

instead <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r course <strong>on</strong> Selected Problems of Pure Phenomenology from a weekly <strong>on</strong>ehour<br />

in<strong>to</strong> a two-hour course (see GA 60: 348; GA 58: 265). It is plausible <strong>to</strong> assume that at least<br />

part of <strong>the</strong> material Heidegger worked through <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> destined for <strong>the</strong> Mysticism course, infi ltrated,<br />

as <strong>to</strong> atmosphere <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> t<strong>on</strong>e, in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenology course. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> occasi<strong>on</strong>al semireligious<br />

characters that this course displays are not just vaguely religious but have a defi nite<br />

tendency <strong>to</strong>wards mysticism, as Heidegger unders<strong>to</strong>od it at <strong>the</strong> time in terms of immediate<br />

religious enactment <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> oppositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rigid cenceptual schemes of Scholasticism. Th e t<strong>on</strong>e<br />

of this religiosity is submissi<strong>on</strong>, humble devoti<strong>on</strong> (for humilitas, see also GA 60: 309; for Hingabe,<br />

ibid., 322), <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> as such it is fairly diff erent from <strong>the</strong> t<strong>on</strong>e of distress <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> fi ght that permeates <strong>the</strong><br />

phenomenology of religi<strong>on</strong> course <strong>on</strong>e year later. For a characteristic occurence of Mitgehen at<br />

<strong>the</strong> Phenomenology of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> course, see GA 60: 72: “die Explikati<strong>on</strong> geht immer mit der<br />

religiösen Erfahrung mit und treibt sie.”


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 115<br />

A comm<strong>on</strong> feature of Heidegger’s criticism of both phenomenology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

life-philosophy is <strong>the</strong> following: both are accused of proceeding not suffi -<br />

ciently unprejudiced. As <strong>to</strong> phenomenology: when viewed more closely, <strong>the</strong><br />

thing itself that it has <strong>to</strong> return <strong>to</strong> as well as <strong>to</strong> center around is not c<strong>on</strong>sciousness,<br />

but life. As <strong>to</strong> life-philosophy: <strong>the</strong> fi eld of research is all right, but <strong>the</strong><br />

approach <strong>to</strong> it is not without bias. Life is approached not as it is being lived<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> enacted, in a lively manner, as it were, but by measures <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<br />

<strong>to</strong>ols alien <strong>to</strong> it which falsify or in any case do not do justice <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> way it does<br />

really come <strong>to</strong> pass.<br />

II. Religious Life As a Paradigm of Facticity<br />

We are now put in a positi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> assess <strong>the</strong> signifi cance of Heidegger’s religi<strong>on</strong><br />

courses for his philosophical development. Th is signifi cance may be spelled out<br />

in a c<strong>on</strong>cise way by summing up his path of thinking from <strong>the</strong> postwar years<br />

up <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> early twenties as follows. Under <strong>the</strong> infl uence of life-philosophy Heidegger<br />

radicalizes Husserlian transcendental phenomenology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> transforms it<br />

in<strong>to</strong> a (hermeneutic) phenomenology of life. Th e phenomenology of life however,<br />

which Heidegger comes <strong>to</strong> elaborate, underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>s itself <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reveals itself,<br />

when looked at more closely, as a phenomenology of religious life. 43<br />

In this formulati<strong>on</strong> two points must be stressed. First, religi<strong>on</strong> is for Heidegger,<br />

in accordance with his distancing himself from <strong>the</strong> Scholastic traditi<strong>on</strong><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> embracing <strong>the</strong> Protestant problematic, primarily life, that is, praxis, not<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, doctrine, or speculati<strong>on</strong>. To put it bluntly: religi<strong>on</strong> is religious life, or<br />

it is not religi<strong>on</strong>. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> can meaningfully be c<strong>on</strong>ceived of <strong>on</strong>ly in terms of<br />

religious life. 44 Th erefore it was entirely appropriate that Heidegger collected<br />

his papers <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> notes pertaining <strong>to</strong> this problematic under <strong>the</strong> designati<strong>on</strong><br />

Phenomenology of Religious Life, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> it was equally a happy decisi<strong>on</strong> that <strong>the</strong><br />

43) With an eye <strong>to</strong> Heidegger’s appropriati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> tranformati<strong>on</strong> of Husserl’s phenomenology, his<br />

coming <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>centrate <strong>on</strong> religi<strong>on</strong> may schematically be put as proceeeding al<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong> following<br />

itinerary:<br />

phenomenology of transcendental c<strong>on</strong>sciousness phenomenology of life phenomenology of religious life.<br />

44) Th is was, again, a widespread tendency of <strong>the</strong> time. “Glaube ist nicht Lehre, s<strong>on</strong>dern Leben,<br />

die erlebte Tatsache [sc. Sache der Tat], der ‘Geburt Gottes’ in der Seele,” Na<strong>to</strong>rp wrote during<br />

<strong>the</strong> war (see Paul Na<strong>to</strong>rp, Deutscher Weltberuf. Geschichtsphilosophische Richtlinien. I. Buch.<br />

Die Weltalter des Geistes [Jena: E. Diederichs 1918], 87; see more <strong>on</strong> this point in my paper<br />

“Heideggers Kritik der On<strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong>ologie,” in Gottes- und <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>sbegriff in der neuzeitlichen Philosophie,<br />

ed. Albert Franz, Wilhelm G. Jacobs [Paderborn: Schöningh, 2000], 200–223).


116 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

edi<strong>to</strong>r chose this title for GA 60. It is also characteristic <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> of importance that<br />

<strong>on</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r envelope Heidegger’s original title was called “Phenomenology of<br />

Religious C<strong>on</strong>ciousness” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that Heidegger later cancelled <strong>the</strong> last word from<br />

this title <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> substituted for it “Life.” 45 Th e substituti<strong>on</strong> of this single word<br />

al<strong>on</strong>e characteristically exhibits Heidegger’s appropriati<strong>on</strong> of, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> attitude <strong>to</strong>,<br />

Husserl’s phenomenology: ra<strong>the</strong>r than c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, it is life that should be<br />

<strong>the</strong> matter for philosophy.<br />

Sec<strong>on</strong>d, it must be noted that in <strong>the</strong> formulati<strong>on</strong>, life is for Heidegger primarily<br />

religious life, <strong>the</strong> two phenomena, life <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> religious life, are not <strong>to</strong> be<br />

sharply distinguished. Nor are <strong>the</strong> two disciplines, phenomenology of life <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

phenomenology of religious life. With regard <strong>to</strong> Heidegger’s repeated rejecti<strong>on</strong><br />

of c<strong>on</strong>ceiving ei<strong>the</strong>r of life or of c<strong>on</strong>sciousness in regi<strong>on</strong>al terms—as object<br />

fi elds cut off from <strong>the</strong> whole of being—it would be misleading <strong>to</strong> think of a<br />

phenomenology of religious life as a kind of subdivisi<strong>on</strong> or specifi cati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

some allegedly comprehensive, all-embracing phenomenology of life. To say<br />

that for Heidegger life is primarily religious life amounts ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> saying that<br />

religious life displays for him in a c<strong>on</strong>centrated way <strong>the</strong> characteristics of<br />

life—that it serves as a sort of paradigm for life. Th ereby Heidegger underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>s<br />

life, inclusive of religious life, in wholly this-worldly terms. Something<br />

such as eternal life or <strong>the</strong> immortality of <strong>the</strong> soul remain out of <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Life is always already factical life, or facticity. Th at is <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong>s why he<br />

focuses his investigati<strong>on</strong>s up<strong>on</strong> Paul’s letters, that is, <strong>the</strong> factical life of <strong>the</strong><br />

earliest Christian communities <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> inner dynamics inherent in <strong>the</strong> (thisworldly)<br />

life of <strong>the</strong> believers bel<strong>on</strong>ging <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Th e dialectics <strong>the</strong>reby in play<br />

is a kind of inverse movement or—<strong>to</strong> borrow Gadamer’s term—a fusi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

horiz<strong>on</strong>s. Religious life does become a paradigm of life for Heidegger, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>on</strong>e h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>; but it is approached <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> viewed with an eye <strong>to</strong> factical life, as a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>centrati<strong>on</strong> of it <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> wholly exempt from all o<strong>the</strong>r-worldly characters,<br />

<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. It is <strong>the</strong> this-worldly living <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> enacting of faith, <strong>the</strong> way <strong>on</strong>e<br />

becomes a Christian <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> lives it all <strong>the</strong> way through, that Heidegger is interested<br />

in <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>centrates up<strong>on</strong>.<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> is, in this perspective, an “object” of study for phenomenological<br />

philosophy much like death becomes <strong>on</strong>e in his main work. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g> centering<br />

around facticity (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> its hermeneutics) must, as l<strong>on</strong>g as it is <strong>to</strong> remain<br />

philosophy, prohibit detaching itself from <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> leaving behind <strong>the</strong> dimensi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

of what shows itself in intuiti<strong>on</strong>. In this respect Heidegger remained for ever<br />

committed <strong>to</strong> Husserl’s “principle of all principles”—more specifi cally, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

45) See GA 60: 345.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 117<br />

prohibitive character inherent in it: everything “off ered <strong>to</strong> us in ‘intuiti<strong>on</strong>’ is<br />

<strong>to</strong> be accepted . . ., but . . . <strong>on</strong>ly within <strong>the</strong> limits in which it is presented <strong>the</strong>re.”<br />

Th e term ‘descripti<strong>on</strong>’ has, in phenomenology, Heidegger argues in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>Time</strong>, “a sense of a prohibiti<strong>on</strong>—<strong>the</strong> avoidance of characterizing anything<br />

without . . . dem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong>.” 46 In full accordance with this principle, he claims<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> work that his “analysis of death remains purely ‘this-worldly’ ”<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that accordingly it decides nothing (ei<strong>the</strong>r positive or negative) about <strong>the</strong><br />

‘o<strong>the</strong>r-worldly.’ Moreover, it even remains undecided whe<strong>the</strong>r any questi<strong>on</strong><br />

c<strong>on</strong>cerning what comes after death can, as a “<strong>the</strong>oretical” (that is, as a phenomenologically<br />

meaningful philosophical) questi<strong>on</strong>, ever be formulated at all. 47<br />

It is worth quoting Heidegger in more detail: “our analysis of death remains<br />

purely ‘this-worldly’ in so far as it interprets that phenomen<strong>on</strong> merely in <strong>the</strong><br />

way in which it enters in<strong>to</strong> any particular Dasein as a possibility of its being.” 48<br />

(“<strong>Being</strong>” should be read here, in terms of his c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality of <strong>the</strong> early twenties,<br />

as “factical <strong>Being</strong>,” “facticity.”) Now we should realize that his approach<br />

<strong>to</strong> religi<strong>on</strong> in <strong>the</strong> early twenties is quite analogous; his c<strong>on</strong>cern is with (<strong>the</strong><br />

phenomenological descripti<strong>on</strong> of) how faith is factically being lived, with<br />

<strong>on</strong>e’s becoming (having become) <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> remaining (becoming again <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> again) a<br />

believer; in short, how <strong>on</strong>e in fact lives <strong>on</strong>e’s faith (whereby faith is a possibility<br />

of <strong>on</strong>e’s factical being). Th e way <strong>on</strong>e does this coincides with <strong>the</strong> way <strong>on</strong>e<br />

lives. Living <strong>the</strong> faith is in no ways separable from living life. By acknowledging<br />

this we are brought back <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> fi rst point, namely, that religi<strong>on</strong> is, fi rst <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

foremost, a matter of praxis, living enactment, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>ory or doctrine.<br />

Indeed faith as practical enactment remains forever <strong>the</strong> fundament of <strong>the</strong>ology<br />

49 (more <strong>on</strong> this later).<br />

But <strong>to</strong> justify <strong>the</strong> claim that religi<strong>on</strong> is primarily religious life is not <strong>to</strong> justify<br />

<strong>the</strong> claim that it is a paradigm of life. So it is still not clear why, in precisely<br />

what sense, religious life is a paradigm of life—why, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, religious<br />

life (characteristic of, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> as experienced in, primal Christianity) provides us<br />

with <strong>the</strong> key—or, more terminologically put, with a phenomenological access—<br />

<strong>to</strong> factical life, or factical life experience; why, as Heideggger states, Christian<br />

religiosity not <strong>on</strong>ly lies (is rooted or grounded or <strong>to</strong> be found) in factical life<br />

46) SZ 35 (“Fernhaltung alles nicht ausweisenden Bestimmens”) / BT 59.<br />

47) SZ 248 / BT 292.<br />

48) SZ 248 / BT 292. Also something such as a “ ‘metaphysics of death’ lies outside <strong>the</strong> domain<br />

of an existential analysis of death” (ibid.).<br />

49) See, for example, GA 60: 95, 145, 310; GA 9: 55, 59, 61; SZ 10.


118 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

experience but is declared <strong>to</strong> coincide with it. For Heidegger’s more radical claim<br />

comes down <strong>to</strong> this: Christian religiosity is factical life experience. 50<br />

Th e recogniti<strong>on</strong> that religi<strong>on</strong> is primarily praxis, life, is clearly not suffi cient<br />

<strong>to</strong> make <strong>the</strong> case plausible, for obviously <strong>the</strong>re may be sorts of practices o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than <strong>the</strong> religious. An explicit answer or c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> is, as far as I can see,<br />

nowhere provided by Heidegger, although this is, admittedly, <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> most<br />

central <strong>the</strong>ses of <strong>the</strong> whole Phenomenology of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> course. In view of his<br />

elucidati<strong>on</strong>s of Paul’s letters as well as his previous fusi<strong>on</strong> of phenomenology<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> life-philosophy, I propose <strong>to</strong> suggest <strong>the</strong> following explanati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

In transforming phenomenology by shifting its focus from transcendental<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sciousness <strong>to</strong> life, Heidegger repeteadly c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ts <strong>the</strong> problem of appropriate<br />

access <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> new subject matter. Life is however a phenomen<strong>on</strong> that is<br />

not at all easy <strong>to</strong> have access <strong>to</strong>. Precisely in virtue of its all-embracing character,<br />

it seems <strong>to</strong> exclude all appropriate access <strong>to</strong> it—such that will not reduce<br />

it <strong>to</strong> a regi<strong>on</strong>al object. Th is much is clearly seen by Heidegger. Indeed, <strong>on</strong>e way<br />

<strong>to</strong> underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his repeated claim that life is characterized by self-suffi ciency 51<br />

is that it does do without philosophy. Heidegger even remarks that life is selfsuffi<br />

cient for itself <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>to</strong> which it is incapable of even seeing that<br />

very self-suffi ciency. 52 After this preliminary remark we should call <strong>to</strong> mind<br />

some of <strong>the</strong> basic features by which Heidegger characterizes Christian life<br />

experience, fi rst of all, <strong>the</strong> character of having-become.<br />

What is characteristic of Christian life is indeed its having-become <strong>on</strong>e. 53<br />

Christian life experience is such that it owes its being <strong>to</strong> its having become,<br />

i.e., <strong>to</strong> its having superseded its previous (sinful, a-<strong>the</strong>istic) 54 state <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> been<br />

born <strong>to</strong> new life. Th e (so <strong>to</strong> speak) transcendental past of always already having<br />

become, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> rebirth, 55 a complete shift in <strong>on</strong>e’s being, 56 is<br />

50) See GA 60: 82: “Urchristliche Religiosität ist in der faktischen Lebenserfahrung. Nachsatz:<br />

Sie ist eigentlich solche selbst.” Th e same point is made in an even more accentuated manner,<br />

ibid., 131: “christliche Religiosität ist in der faktischen Lebenserfahrung, ist sie eigentlich selbst.”<br />

(Italics in original.)<br />

51) See GA 58: 29, 30f., 35, 41, 63.<br />

52) GA 58: 41. Ibid 61: Heidegger makes <strong>the</strong> point that Christianity is a his<strong>to</strong>rical paradigm for<br />

centering life for <strong>the</strong> fi rst time around <strong>the</strong> self-world. Th is accent <strong>on</strong> individuality, i.e., <strong>the</strong> individually<br />

centered character of life, will lead up <strong>to</strong> Dasein’s Jemeinigkeit in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>, while<br />

<strong>the</strong> term Selbstwelt disappears.<br />

53) See GA 60: 93ff .<br />

54) See GA 9: 53 (“Gottvergessenheit”).<br />

55) See GA 9: 53 (Glaube = Wiedergeburt”). See also ibid., 63.<br />

56) GA 60: 95: “absolute Umwendung,” “Hinwendung zu Gott und eine Wegwendung v<strong>on</strong> den<br />

Götzenbildern.”


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 119<br />

entirely c<strong>on</strong>stitutive for Christian experience of life. It is a shift in being, which<br />

at <strong>the</strong> very moment of becoming aware of itself, gains awareness of itself in<br />

terms of a being that has become what it actually is. It is solely because it has<br />

become what it is that it is what it is—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> it does also have a specifi c awareness<br />

of it. Indeed, Christian experience of life is not <strong>on</strong>ly characterized by<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that it has become what it is but also, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> with equal primordiality,<br />

by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> event of having become is accompanied by some kind of<br />

a c<strong>on</strong>sciousness of having become, no less than of <strong>the</strong> fact that this havingbecome<br />

has not been initiated <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> performed by itself. 57 By all means, its<br />

having-become bel<strong>on</strong>gs in an indispensable <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> irrevocable way <strong>to</strong> its present<br />

being. 58<br />

Now it is my claim that it is because it is not possible <strong>to</strong> be a Christian<br />

without having this specifi c kind of “knowledge” (indeed, a hermeneutic preunderst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing)<br />

of being <strong>on</strong>e—namely, of having become or been reborn by<br />

divine grace <strong>to</strong> be <strong>on</strong>e, of st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing presently before God <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reaching escha<strong>to</strong>logically<br />

forward <strong>to</strong>ward <strong>the</strong> imminent future, running ahead against it—<br />

that Christian life experience may reas<strong>on</strong>ably be claimed <strong>to</strong> experience life in<br />

its facticity, <strong>to</strong> be factical life experience. Christian religiosity, or Christian life<br />

experience, in terms of an experience of having become, opens up (a perspective<br />

or <strong>the</strong> perspective up<strong>on</strong>) factical life for <strong>the</strong> fi rst time, <strong>the</strong>refore it is factical<br />

life experience. Factical life <strong>the</strong>reby gets disclosed <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> becomes accessible for<br />

<strong>the</strong> fi rst time as such—that is, as factical life, a specifi cally <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> defi nitely thisworldly<br />

life. It is due <strong>to</strong> this having become (<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, inseparably from it, <strong>the</strong><br />

awareness which accompanies it) that factical life is opened up. Indeed, Christian<br />

life experience does experience <strong>the</strong> whole of life—past, present, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

future—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> thus lives temporality. It is not <strong>on</strong>ly in time but it is time. 59 It<br />

focuses <strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> centers around its having become. 60 Th e state it has overcome<br />

57) See GA 60: 121f.<br />

58) See esp. GA 60: 94: “Das Wissen über das eigene Gewordensein stellt der Explikati<strong>on</strong> eine<br />

ganz bes<strong>on</strong>dere Aufgabe. Hieraus wird sich der Sinn einer Faktizität bestimmen, die v<strong>on</strong> einem<br />

bestimmten Wissen begleitet ist. Wir reißen die Faktizität und das Wissen ausein<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>er, aber sie<br />

ist ganz urspünglich miterfahren. . . . Das Gewordensein ist nun nicht ein beliebiges Vorkommnis<br />

im Leben, s<strong>on</strong>dern es wird ständig miterfahren und zwar so, daß ihr jetziges Sein Gewordensein<br />

ist. Ihr Gewordensein ist ihr jetziges Sein.” See also ibid., 145: “Faktizität, zu der ja das<br />

‘Wissen’ gehört.” Fur<strong>the</strong>r, ibid., 93: “Wissen v<strong>on</strong> ihrem Gewordensein”; 103, 123, etc.<br />

59) See GA 60: 80, 82, 104, 116.<br />

60) See GA 60: 120: “Das christliche Leben ist nicht geradelinig, s<strong>on</strong>dern ist gebrochen: Alle umweltlichen<br />

Bezüge müssen hindurchgehen durch den Vollzugszusammenhang des Gewordenseins.”


120 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

remains, although fundamentally changed, forever included in it. 61 Th ose who<br />

fi nd <strong>the</strong>mselves in a pre-Christian state are not “awake,” have no awareness of<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves, do not possess life experience because <strong>the</strong>y simply do not experience<br />

life in its factical <strong>to</strong>tality. Only <strong>the</strong> rebirth, as it were, opens up access <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> fi rst birth. Th e case is similar <strong>to</strong> what it will be with respect <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> au<strong>the</strong>nticinau<strong>the</strong>ntic<br />

distincti<strong>on</strong> in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong> (which may be seen <strong>to</strong> be a specifi c<br />

subsequent elaborati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> this state of aff airs): inau<strong>the</strong>ntic being always<br />

already precedes au<strong>the</strong>ntic being, which in its turn erects itself up<strong>on</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> has<br />

as its fundament, <strong>the</strong> inau<strong>the</strong>ntic. It is <strong>on</strong>ly after having performed <strong>the</strong> passage<br />

from <strong>the</strong> inau<strong>the</strong>ntic <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntic that inau<strong>the</strong>ntic being as such—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with it, <strong>the</strong> very distincti<strong>on</strong> itself—becomes fi rst disclosed <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> accessible.<br />

For <strong>to</strong> be inau<strong>the</strong>ntic means having no awareness of being inau<strong>the</strong>ntic<br />

(just like <strong>the</strong> self-suffi ciency of life works against its own becoming aware<br />

of it). And vice versa: <strong>to</strong> be au<strong>the</strong>ntic means gaining awareness of <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> assuming<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sciously <strong>on</strong>e’s inau<strong>the</strong>nticity as a past that has always already preceded<br />

it <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that <strong>the</strong>refore—in its specifi c quality as a past always already surpassed<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> overcome—bel<strong>on</strong>gs intrinsically <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> inextricably forever <strong>to</strong> au<strong>the</strong>nticity.<br />

Facticity, His<strong>to</strong>ricity, Christianity<br />

A point that is worth special attenti<strong>on</strong> in this c<strong>on</strong>text is Heidegger’s repeated<br />

claim that factical life or life experience is intrinsically his<strong>to</strong>rical. As has been<br />

noted, <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>temporary tendencies with which Heidegger engaged in<br />

in-depth c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> from <strong>the</strong> very beginning was his<strong>to</strong>ricism. Th e idea that<br />

life <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his<strong>to</strong>ry bel<strong>on</strong>g intimately <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r—that life should primarily be<br />

seen as his<strong>to</strong>rical life—was central <strong>to</strong> Dil<strong>the</strong>y <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> life-philosophy in general.<br />

Heidegger appreciated very much indeed 62 Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s attempt <strong>to</strong> approach his<strong>to</strong>rical<br />

life but criticized him for reas<strong>on</strong>s analogous <strong>to</strong> those he formulated<br />

about his approach <strong>to</strong> life—that is, <strong>the</strong> inadaquate c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality rooted in<br />

a <strong>on</strong>e-sided <strong>the</strong>oretical comportment. Although Dil<strong>the</strong>y did tend <strong>to</strong> grasp<br />

his<strong>to</strong>rical life, his endeavor came under <strong>the</strong> infl uence of neo-Kantianism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>the</strong> erkenntnis<strong>the</strong>oretisch atmosphere of <strong>the</strong> age, so that he ultimately misunders<strong>to</strong>od<br />

his own undertaking: <strong>the</strong> attempt at a new <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> fresh access <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical<br />

life was reduced <strong>to</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> replaced by, <strong>the</strong> attempt <strong>to</strong> attain possibly<br />

objective his<strong>to</strong>rical knowledge <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> thus <strong>to</strong> elevate his<strong>to</strong>ry <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rank of<br />

61) See GA 9: 63: “in der gläubigen Existenz das überwundene vorchristliche Dasein existenzial<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logisch<br />

mitbeschlossen bleibt.”<br />

62) See <strong>the</strong> references in note 27 above.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 121<br />

science. 63 His<strong>to</strong>ry—or ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical world—became for Dil<strong>the</strong>y an<br />

object of science, something that in its embarrassing richness of types <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

fi gures <strong>on</strong>e takes pleasure in c<strong>on</strong>templating. What mattered was no more his<strong>to</strong>rical<br />

being but his<strong>to</strong>rical knowledge <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with its claim <strong>to</strong> objective<br />

validity, whereby <strong>the</strong> subject of that knowledge was a de-situated timeless<br />

observer ra<strong>the</strong>r than his<strong>to</strong>rically rooted <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> existentially involved fi nite existence.<br />

In summary, Heidegger works out his all important c<strong>on</strong>cept of “das<br />

His<strong>to</strong>rische” in his early lecture courses in sheer oppositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ricism, <strong>the</strong><br />

main critical suggesti<strong>on</strong> being that his<strong>to</strong>ricism strives for an “objective” knowledge<br />

of his<strong>to</strong>ry (an impossible aim), ra<strong>the</strong>r than for an au<strong>the</strong>ntic his<strong>to</strong>rical<br />

“being” of humans—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that <strong>the</strong> fi rst not so much promotes <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d but<br />

instead suppresses it. 64<br />

Against <strong>the</strong> background of this criticism Heidegger endeavors <strong>to</strong> reappropriate<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical dimensi<strong>on</strong> of his<strong>to</strong>ricism <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> gain access <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ry in<br />

terms of his<strong>to</strong>rical being. Th ereby he does not fail <strong>to</strong> acknowledge his indebtedness<br />

<strong>to</strong> Dil<strong>the</strong>y <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> claim, eventually, that his c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of his<strong>to</strong>ry grew<br />

out of an appropriati<strong>on</strong> of Dil<strong>the</strong>y’work. 65 In his postwar lecture courses, he<br />

notes frequently that by stressing <strong>the</strong> importance of his<strong>to</strong>ry, he has in mind<br />

his<strong>to</strong>ry primarily not as a matter of scholarship. To put it bluntly: our knowing<br />

relati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ry is <strong>on</strong>ly a derivative <strong>on</strong>e, <strong>the</strong> primary relati<strong>on</strong> is <strong>on</strong>e of<br />

being—we are his<strong>to</strong>ry. Th e way we live his<strong>to</strong>ry, or are his<strong>to</strong>ry, is dependent<br />

up<strong>on</strong> how we live temporality. His<strong>to</strong>ry is primarily his<strong>to</strong>ricity, that is, Geschehen,<br />

of a specifi c being called Dasein—it is <strong>the</strong> movement of its erstrecktes<br />

Sicherstrecken, its stretching al<strong>on</strong>g between birth <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> death. 66 Th e way his<strong>to</strong>ry<br />

becomes object for scientifi c investigati<strong>on</strong> is decided from time <strong>to</strong> time by<br />

<strong>the</strong> primordial his<strong>to</strong>ricity of Dasein. Th is positi<strong>on</strong> is clearly anticipated in<br />

<strong>the</strong> early lecture courses. His<strong>to</strong>ry, Heidegger says, for example in 1919/20, is<br />

not critique of <strong>the</strong> sources but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, living al<strong>on</strong>g with life (mitlebendes<br />

63) See, for example, GA 17: 301 (Dil<strong>the</strong>y fell victim <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong>al questi<strong>on</strong>, how is his<strong>to</strong>ry<br />

of science as science possible?). See also, ibid., 302.<br />

64) Th e term “das His<strong>to</strong>rische” will be replaced in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong> by “das Geschichtliche,” or<br />

“Geschichtlichkeit.” For later, see <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> between “geschichtliche und his<strong>to</strong>rische Wahrheit”<br />

in GA 39: 144ff , viz., that between “his<strong>to</strong>rische Betrachtung” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> “geschichtliche Besinnung” in<br />

GA 45: 34ff ., 49ff ., 88ff . Fur<strong>the</strong>r, see also GA 45: 11ff ., 40, 201; GA 65: 32f., 151f. 153 (“Die<br />

His<strong>to</strong>rie . . . ist ein ständiges Ausweichen vor der Geschichte”), 359, 421f., 493f.<br />

65) See SZ 397.<br />

66) See SZ 19f., 375, 374f. / BT 40f., 427, 425f. “[T]he locus of <strong>the</strong> problem of his<strong>to</strong>ry . . . is not<br />

<strong>to</strong> be sought in his<strong>to</strong>riology as <strong>the</strong> science of his<strong>to</strong>ry” (SZ 375 / BT 427).


122 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

Leben), life’s familiarity with itself, 67 or—as he puts it in <strong>the</strong> Phenomenology<br />

of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> course in 1920/21—“immediate liveliness” (unmittelbare Lebendigkeit).<br />

68 Also, he keeps warning against <strong>the</strong> widespread habit of having access <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> phenomen<strong>on</strong> of his<strong>to</strong>ry as it is delivered over <strong>to</strong> us by his<strong>to</strong>rical science. 69<br />

But—what is particularly important for us—he tends <strong>to</strong> identify <strong>the</strong> factical<br />

with <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical. Th e his<strong>to</strong>rical, he says, is inherent in <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> intrinsic <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning of <strong>the</strong> factical. 70 Th e sense of <strong>the</strong> factical points <strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> leads up <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical.<br />

Since, as has been seen, religious life off ers a paradigm of facticity, it is<br />

no w<strong>on</strong>der that <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical is thus ultimately brought back <strong>to</strong> religious life<br />

experience as well. “Th e entire task of a phenomenology of religi<strong>on</strong> . . . is permeated<br />

by <strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical,” Heidegger claims explicitly. 71 To<br />

underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> this point, we should bear in mind that it is not because Dasein is<br />

his<strong>to</strong>rical that it is temporal, but <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way round. Dasein’s temporality is<br />

<strong>the</strong> fundament of its his<strong>to</strong>ricity. 72 Although formulated in explicit terms in<br />

<strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>, this <strong>the</strong>sis is however present at <strong>the</strong> religi<strong>on</strong> courses. 73 Th e fact<br />

that, by virtue of its having become, Christian life experience becomes uniquely<br />

temporal, that is, it lives time, it is time, accounts for, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> is <strong>the</strong> fundament of,<br />

its entering in<strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> partaking most intimately of <strong>the</strong> innermost event that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>stitutes Christianity.<br />

Heidegger’s gradual disengaging <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> distancing himself from neo-Scholastic<br />

thinking during <strong>the</strong> war <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his c<strong>on</strong>current turn <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Protestant traditi<strong>on</strong><br />

had obviously, <strong>to</strong> a large extent, predisposed him favorably <strong>to</strong>ward <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me<br />

of his<strong>to</strong>ry in terms of a domain which—over against its dismissal by neo-<br />

Scholasticism—was very much pertinent <strong>to</strong> religi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> religiosity. In fact, as<br />

he put it in his letter <strong>to</strong> Engelbert Krebs written <strong>on</strong> January 9, 1919, it was<br />

“epistemological insights, extending as far as <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of his<strong>to</strong>rical knowledge,”<br />

that “have made <strong>the</strong> system of Catholicism problematic <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> unaccept-<br />

67) GA 58: 159f.<br />

68) GA 60: 33.<br />

69) See, for example, GA 60: 32, 47, 51f.<br />

70) GA 61: 76 (“Die Faktizität des Lebens . . . ist in sich selbst his<strong>to</strong>risch . . .” “. . . das His<strong>to</strong>rische<br />

im Sinn der Faktizität liegt”), 159 (“Faktizität: das Geschichtliche, das His<strong>to</strong>rische”).<br />

71) GA 60: 34. See ibid., 323.<br />

72) See SZ 376.<br />

73) See GA 60: 65: “Was ist in der faktischen Lebenserfahrung ursprünglich die Zeitlichkeit?”<br />

“. . . unser Weg geht vom faktischen Leben aus, v<strong>on</strong> dem aus der Sinn v<strong>on</strong> Zeit gew<strong>on</strong>nen wird.<br />

Damit ist das Problem des His<strong>to</strong>rischen gekennzeichnet.” See also, ibid., 80: “Die faktische<br />

Lebenserfahrung ist his<strong>to</strong>risch. Die christliche Religiosität lebt die Zeitlichkeit als solche.”


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 123<br />

able” <strong>to</strong> him. 74 Th ereby <strong>the</strong> system he had in mind was most plausibly <strong>the</strong><br />

offi cial doctrine of neo-Th omistic Scholasticism, exempt <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> immune from<br />

all his<strong>to</strong>ricity. Th is is c<strong>on</strong>fi rmed by <strong>the</strong> fact that, much in this vein, <strong>the</strong> system<br />

is referred <strong>to</strong> in a highly negative t<strong>on</strong>e in <strong>the</strong> lecture course <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> Phenomenology<br />

of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>, namely, in terms of a kind of “pseudo-philosophy,” whereby<br />

Heidegger menti<strong>on</strong>s paren<strong>the</strong>tically “Catholicism” as an example; what is<br />

characteristic of <strong>the</strong> system is that access <strong>to</strong> its living sense must be attained by<br />

working <strong>on</strong>e’s way through a complicated, inorganic, wholly unclear <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> dogmatic<br />

complex of <strong>the</strong>ses <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> proofs, sancti<strong>on</strong>ed by policy c<strong>on</strong>straint of <strong>the</strong><br />

church <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> oppressing <strong>the</strong> subject. 75 Th e “<strong>the</strong>ory of his<strong>to</strong>rical knowledge,” <strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, obviously points <strong>to</strong> Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s eff orts <strong>to</strong> elaborate what he called<br />

a critique of his<strong>to</strong>rical reas<strong>on</strong>. 76 In precisely what sense (or <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>to</strong> which)<br />

<strong>the</strong> “<strong>the</strong>ory of his<strong>to</strong>rical knowledge”—<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> orientati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong>wards <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical<br />

in general—though in sharp c<strong>on</strong>trast <strong>to</strong> ahis<strong>to</strong>rical Scholasticism, was<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less able <strong>to</strong> preserve <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> even embrace <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> reinforce Heidegger’s religious<br />

impulse is shown by <strong>the</strong> following notes from Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s diary: “it is my<br />

vocati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> grasp <strong>the</strong> inner essence of religious life in his<strong>to</strong>ry”; “Christianity<br />

74) “. . . but not Christianity <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> metaphysics (<strong>the</strong> latter, <strong>to</strong> be sure, in a new sense),” he fi nishes his<br />

sentence, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> this complement is surely not insignifi cant, for it shows Heidegger’s c<strong>on</strong>tinuing <strong>to</strong> be<br />

in <strong>the</strong> proximity, although “in a new sense,” <strong>to</strong> Christianity <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> metaphysics. Th e letter was fi rst<br />

published by Bernhard Casper, “Martin Heidegger und die Th eologische Fakultät Freiburg 1909–<br />

1923,” in Kirche am Oberrhein. Festschrift für Wolfgang Müller, ed. R. Bäumer, K. Suso Frank, Hugo<br />

Ott (Freiburg i. Br.: Herder, 1980), 541; see now Heidegger-Jahrbuch, vol. 1: Heidegger und<br />

die Anfänge seines Denkens, ed. Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth G<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>er, Holger Zaborowski<br />

(Freiburg: Alber, 2004), 67f. I have adopted John D. Capu<strong>to</strong>’s translati<strong>on</strong> in his Heidegger <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

Aquinas, 56f. To say that <strong>the</strong> “system of Catholicism” has become “problematic <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> unacceptable”<br />

is <strong>to</strong> say that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ological-philosophical foundati<strong>on</strong> that underlies faith—<strong>the</strong> fundament, <strong>the</strong><br />

groundwork, up<strong>on</strong> which faith rests—has become obsolete <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> hollow, requiring, as it does, being<br />

renewed <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> refreshed. To fulfi l this task is in no way c<strong>on</strong>trary <strong>to</strong> Christian faith. For more detailed<br />

interpretati<strong>on</strong> of this letter, see my paper “Heidegger’s Underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of <strong>the</strong> A<strong>the</strong>ism of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g>:<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g>, Th eology, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> in his Early Lecture Courses up <strong>to</strong> <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>,” American<br />

Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 69, 2 (Spring 1995): 189–228.<br />

75) GA 60: 313: “liegt es a priori in der Struktur des Systems, das selbst nicht einer organischen<br />

Kulturtat entwachsen ist, daß der zu erlebende Wertgehalt der <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> als solcher, ihre inhaltliche<br />

Sinnsphäre erst durch ein verwickeltes unorganisches, <strong>the</strong>oretisch völlig ungeklärtes, dogmatisches<br />

Gehege v<strong>on</strong> Sätzen und Beweisgängen hindurch muß, um schließlich als kirchenrechtliche<br />

Satzung mit Polizeigewalt das Subjekt zu überwältigen und dunkel zu belasten und zu erdrücken.”<br />

76) See Wilhelm Dil<strong>the</strong>y, Der Ausbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften, vol. 7<br />

of Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Bernhard Groethuysen, 7th ed. (Göttingen: V<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>enhoeck & Ruprecht,<br />

1979), 191ff .


124 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

is not a system, but a life-view.” 77 And in Schleiermacher, <strong>to</strong> whom Dil<strong>the</strong>y<br />

dedicated no small porti<strong>on</strong> of his life work <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> who also attracted Heidegger’s<br />

attenti<strong>on</strong> during <strong>the</strong> war, 78 we can read <strong>the</strong> following remark: “His<strong>to</strong>ry, unders<strong>to</strong>od<br />

in <strong>the</strong> most appropriate sense, is <strong>the</strong> highest object of religi<strong>on</strong>; it is with<br />

his<strong>to</strong>ry that religi<strong>on</strong> begins <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> it ends up with it as well.” 79<br />

It is certainly no mere incident, but plausibly a sign of approval, that<br />

Heidegger literally excerpted this passage in his notes <strong>on</strong> Schleiermacher. 80<br />

And somewhat later he noted: “Th e his<strong>to</strong>rical is <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> most signifi cant<br />

founding elements in religious experience.” 81 If we add <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se remarks<br />

Heidegger’s central claim c<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> mutual identifi cati<strong>on</strong> of his<strong>to</strong>ricity<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> facticity—<strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> most characteristic formulati<strong>on</strong>s is this: “[h]is<strong>to</strong>ry<br />

77) Der junge Dil<strong>the</strong>y. Ein Lebensbild in Briefen und Tagebüchern 1852–1870, ed. Clara Misch<br />

(Leipzig: Teubner, 1933), 140: “mein Beruf ist, das Innerste des religiösen Lebens in der His<strong>to</strong>rie<br />

zu erfassen” (italics in original); 144: “das Christenthum kein System, s<strong>on</strong>dern eine Lebensanschauung<br />

ist.” See <strong>the</strong> same claim in Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s main work: Wilhelm Dil<strong>the</strong>y, Einleitung in die<br />

Geisteswissenschaften. Versuch einer Grundlegung für das Studium der Gesellschaft und der Geschichte,<br />

in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 1, ed. Bernhard Groethuysen, 9th ed. (Göttingen: V<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>enhoeck &<br />

Ruprecht, 1990), 138f, 253f. (“das religiöse Leben . . . Untergrund des geschichtlichen Lebens”;<br />

“die Philosophie des Christentums . . . trug eine machvolle geschichtliche Realität in sich”). For<br />

<strong>the</strong> term Faktizität in Dil<strong>the</strong>y, see ibid., 141. Th e term Lebensanschauung (life-view) in <strong>the</strong> above<br />

quotati<strong>on</strong> is clearly of Schleiermacherian origin.<br />

78) In early August of 1917 Heidegger gave privately an impressive talk <strong>on</strong> Schleiermacher’s<br />

Reden über die <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>. He stressed especially Schleiermacher’s rejecti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> philosophical<br />

<strong>the</strong>ology from Aris<strong>to</strong>tle <strong>to</strong> Hegel. On this point, see Ot<strong>to</strong> Pöggeler, Neue Wege mit Heidegger<br />

(Freiburg: Alber, 1992), 21f.<br />

79) Friedrich Daniel Ernst Schleiermacher, Über die <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>. Reden an die Gebildeten unter ihren<br />

Verächtern, ed. Rudolf Ot<strong>to</strong>, 4th revised ed. (Göttingen: V<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>enhoeck & Ruprecht, 1920), 63. For<br />

Schleiermacher’s rejecti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> philosophical <strong>the</strong>ology, see ibid., 26ff ., 31, 47, 73, 76, 79, 112, etc.<br />

In <strong>on</strong>e important document of Schelling’s, <strong>the</strong> written draft related <strong>to</strong> his lecture course of 1831/32<br />

in Munich, we can read that “<strong>the</strong> essence of Christianity is <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical [das Geschichtliche],” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

that it is not correct always <strong>to</strong> speak about “Christ’s doctrine” [Lehre], ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way round:<br />

“this doctrine is Christ himself” (Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, Urfassung der Philosophie der<br />

Off enbarung, ed. W. E. Ehrhardt, 2 vols. [Hamburg: Meiner, 1992], Teilb<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1, 17).<br />

80) See GA 60: 322. Th e <strong>on</strong>ly change is that Heidegger italicizes “his<strong>to</strong>ry”, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> this, of course,<br />

gives <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> identifi cati<strong>on</strong> of his<strong>to</strong>ry <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> religi<strong>on</strong> more prominence. It will be of use <strong>to</strong> quote <strong>the</strong><br />

full sentence of Schleiermacher: “Geschichte im eigentlichsten Sinn ist der höchste Gegenst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

der <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>, mit ihr hebt sie an und endigt mit ihr—denn Weissagung ist in ihren Augen auch<br />

Geschichte und beides gar nicht v<strong>on</strong>ein<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>er zu unterscheiden—und alle wahre Geschichte hat<br />

überall zuerst einen religiösen Zweck gehabt und ist v<strong>on</strong> religiösen Ideen aus gegangen” (Über die<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>, 63).<br />

81) GA 60: 323.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 125<br />

applies <strong>to</strong>/aff ects us, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> we are his<strong>to</strong>ry itself” 82 —<strong>the</strong>n we arrive ultimately<br />

at a threefold identifi cati<strong>on</strong>. From this perspective, facticity, his<strong>to</strong>ry, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

religi<strong>on</strong>—in o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>to</strong> be factical, <strong>to</strong> be his<strong>to</strong>rical, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> be religious—<br />

become mutually dependent up<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> grow intimately fused with each o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

Th ereby <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical, as it were, unites in itself <strong>the</strong> religious <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> Lebensphilosophische—a<br />

tribute paid <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> memory of Dil<strong>the</strong>y.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>: <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g>, Facticity of Hermeneutics, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>, Faith,<br />

Th eology<br />

Shortly after Heidegger had accepted <strong>the</strong> call <strong>to</strong> Marburg, Gadamer recalls a<br />

remark Heidegger made during an evening discussi<strong>on</strong>: “in order <strong>to</strong> come back<br />

<strong>to</strong> itself, it is <strong>the</strong> true task of <strong>the</strong>ology <strong>to</strong> look for <strong>the</strong> word capable of calling<br />

<strong>on</strong>e <strong>to</strong> faith <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> of preserving <strong>on</strong>e in it.” Th is formulati<strong>on</strong> sounded, for<br />

Gadamer, like a real assignment for <strong>the</strong>ology. Gadamer thinks that <strong>the</strong> real<br />

questi<strong>on</strong>s that were stirring in Heidegger from <strong>the</strong> very beginning were <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

questi<strong>on</strong>s. 83<br />

Th e analogous view is expressed by Gadamer’s choice of <strong>the</strong> very title of his<br />

accompanying essay <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> publicati<strong>on</strong> of Heidegger’s so called Na<strong>to</strong>rp Report<br />

(or Aris<strong>to</strong>tle Introducti<strong>on</strong>), discovered at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> 1980s, “Heidegger’s<br />

Early ‘Th eological’ Writing.” Th is title, <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with his explana<strong>to</strong>ry remark<br />

that it (no less than Hermann Nohl’s title for what he called Hegel’s Early<br />

Th eological Writings) is both appropriate <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> inappropriate, 84 might well characterize,<br />

in additi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> this particular manuscript, no small porti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong><br />

young Heidegger’s work. As a matter of fact, <strong>the</strong> underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of philosophy<br />

Heidegger is working out right after <strong>the</strong> war is interwoven with <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

motives, while (parallel with it) he embarks <strong>on</strong> an overall reexaminati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ology <strong>to</strong>o, including its task, functi<strong>on</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> relati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> religi<strong>on</strong>. Th e selfinterpretati<strong>on</strong><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> self-identifi cati<strong>on</strong> as a philosopher, which he comes <strong>to</strong> adopt,<br />

is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>al up<strong>on</strong> an underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of philosophy that is permeated by <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

motives or may even be said <strong>to</strong> emerge owing <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

82) GA 60: 173: “Die Geschichte triff t uns, und wir sind sie selbst . . .”<br />

83) Hans-Georg Gadamer, “Die Marburger Th eologie,” in Gadamer, Neuere Philosophie. I. Hegel,<br />

Husserl, Heidegger, vol. 3 of Gesammelte Werke (Tübingen: Mohr, 1987), 197, 199; see also Philosophische<br />

Lehrjahre (Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann, 1977), 37.<br />

84) Hans-Georg Gadamer, “Heideggers ‘<strong>the</strong>ologische’ Jugendschrift,” in Martin Heidegger, Phänomenologische<br />

Interpretati<strong>on</strong>en zu Aris<strong>to</strong>teles. Ausarbeitung für die Marburger und die Göttinger<br />

Philosophische Fakultät (1922), ed. Günter Neumann (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2002), 76.


126 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

<strong>the</strong>ological or religious motives. Th e o<strong>the</strong>r side of this process is that Heidegger<br />

puts in<strong>to</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong>al self-underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of <strong>the</strong>ology <strong>to</strong>o, inclusive of<br />

its relati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> philosophy. Th e extent <strong>to</strong> which Heidegger views philosophy <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>the</strong>ology in proximity <strong>to</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> as mutually permeating, <strong>on</strong>e ano<strong>the</strong>r is characteristically<br />

shown by his urge, in his course <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> Phenomenology of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>, <strong>to</strong><br />

submit both of <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong> his central operati<strong>on</strong> of destructi<strong>on</strong>; in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with<br />

<strong>the</strong> interpretat<strong>on</strong> of Paul’s letters, he speaks about elaborating <strong>the</strong> st<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ards for<br />

“<strong>the</strong> destructi<strong>on</strong> of Christian <strong>the</strong>ology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Western philosophy.” 85<br />

In his above cited letter <strong>to</strong> Karl Löwith <strong>on</strong> August 19, 1921, Heidegger<br />

claimed <strong>to</strong> be, ra<strong>the</strong>r than a philosopher, a “Christian <strong>the</strong>ologian.” It is precisely<br />

Gadamer’s s<strong>to</strong>ry that may provide us with a key <strong>to</strong> underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing <strong>the</strong><br />

peculiar italicizati<strong>on</strong>. In fact, it should be taken <strong>to</strong> mean some<strong>on</strong>e searching for<br />

<strong>the</strong> proper logos, that is, word, of <strong>the</strong> Christian message. I think that Gadamer’s<br />

recollecti<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cerning Heidegger’s underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of <strong>the</strong> “task of <strong>the</strong>ology” in<br />

terms of “looking for <strong>the</strong> word capable of calling <strong>on</strong>e <strong>to</strong> faith <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> of preserving<br />

<strong>on</strong>e in it” is highly credible <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> is, indeed, a fairly precise formulati<strong>on</strong>. As a<br />

fi nal c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> I propose <strong>to</strong> show this by a short interpretive rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong><br />

of how Heidegger came <strong>to</strong> view <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong> of religi<strong>on</strong>, faith, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>ology<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> of how <strong>the</strong>se are related <strong>to</strong> philosophy <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> hermeneutics.<br />

Against <strong>the</strong> background of his distancing himself from neo-Scholasticism<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> of his assimilati<strong>on</strong> of decisive motives of life-philosophy <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his<strong>to</strong>ricism,<br />

inclusive of his overall attack against <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical, 86 Heidegger comes <strong>to</strong><br />

view <strong>the</strong>ology no more in terms of an objective <strong>the</strong>oretical science destined <strong>to</strong><br />

provide a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual elaborati<strong>on</strong> for religi<strong>on</strong> by occasi<strong>on</strong>ally borrowing its<br />

c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality from philosophy. Th eology is not a scientifi cally neutral <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

ahis<strong>to</strong>rical <strong>the</strong>ory of Christianity; what has been developed <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> come <strong>to</strong> be<br />

known as <strong>the</strong>ology during <strong>the</strong> centuries is a reifi ed mixture of dead formulae<br />

of <strong>the</strong> most heterogeneous origin, alienated from what it <strong>on</strong>ce bel<strong>on</strong>ged <strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

incapable of c<strong>on</strong>taining in itself <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>veying living religiosity. Th e comportment<br />

it originates from is <strong>the</strong>oretical ra<strong>the</strong>r than religious. Th eoretical comportment,<br />

in its turn, goes back <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Greeks. Primal Christianity was thus<br />

fused with, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> indeed dis<strong>to</strong>rted by, <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality of Greek philosophy, 87<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that is how what we know in terms of <strong>the</strong>ology <strong>to</strong>day came in<strong>to</strong> being.<br />

Th ereby Heidegger seems <strong>to</strong> subscribe <strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> join in with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n widespread<br />

<strong>the</strong>sis c<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> fateful hellenizati<strong>on</strong> of Christianity, suggested, for<br />

85) GA 60: 135: “Destrukti<strong>on</strong> der christlichen Th eologie und der abendländischen Philosophie.”<br />

86) See GA 56/57: 59 <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> note 32 above.<br />

87) See GA 59: 91.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 127<br />

example, by Adolf v<strong>on</strong> Harnack <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> maintained decisively by Franz Overbeck.<br />

88 What is needed is a <strong>the</strong>ology liberated from <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceptual schemes of<br />

Greek philosophy. 89 Th erefore, Heidegger urges in his course <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> Phenomenology<br />

of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> “<strong>to</strong> sharply distinguish <strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>the</strong>ology from that<br />

of religi<strong>on</strong>.” 90 What it comes down <strong>to</strong> is—much al<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong> lines of Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s<br />

linking of Erleben <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Ausdruck—<strong>to</strong> fi nd a proper logos, a c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality adequate<br />

<strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>forming <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> “object,” that is, genuine religious experience<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> faith as a living enactment.<br />

We fi nd an important follow-up observati<strong>on</strong> in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong>. Th eology,<br />

Heidegger claims, “is slowly beginning <strong>to</strong> underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong>ce more Lu<strong>the</strong>r’s<br />

insight, that <strong>the</strong> ‘foundati<strong>on</strong>’ <strong>on</strong> which its system of dogma rests has not arisen<br />

from an inquiry in which faith is primary, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> that c<strong>on</strong>ceptually this ‘foundati<strong>on</strong>’<br />

not <strong>on</strong>ly is inadequate for <strong>the</strong> problematic of <strong>the</strong>ology, but c<strong>on</strong>ceals <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

dis<strong>to</strong>rts it” (SZ 10/ BT 30; see GA 20: 6/4.) In his lecture “Phenomenology<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Th eology,” held in <strong>the</strong> same year of <strong>the</strong> publicati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<strong>Time</strong>, Heidegger interprets <strong>the</strong>ology, much in <strong>the</strong> same vein, as <strong>the</strong> “science<br />

88) See Adolf v<strong>on</strong> Harnack, Lehrbuch der Dogmengeschichte, 3 vols., 4th ed. (1909/10; Reprogh.<br />

Nachdruck. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1983), vol 1, 20: “Das Dogma ist<br />

in seiner C<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> und in seinem Ausbau ein Werk des griechischen Geistes auf dem Boden<br />

des Evangeliums.” Heidegger refers <strong>to</strong> Harnack in GA 60: 72, claiming it is precisely <strong>the</strong> seemingly<br />

sec<strong>on</strong>dary problem of “expressi<strong>on</strong>,” of “religious explicati<strong>on</strong>” <strong>to</strong> be of decisive importance,<br />

for <strong>the</strong> “explicati<strong>on</strong>” goes h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> in h<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> with <strong>the</strong> religious experience. Th is is much in line with<br />

Gadamer’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> that <strong>the</strong>ology has, for Heidegger, primarily <strong>to</strong> do with fi nding <strong>the</strong><br />

adequate “word,” i.e., c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality, <strong>to</strong> express faith. Heidegger’s own subsequent formulati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

what dogma is shows Harnack’s obvious infl uence. See GA 60: 112: “Das Dogma als abgelöster<br />

Lehrgehalt in objektiv-erkenntnismäßiger Abhebung kann niemals leitend für die christliche<br />

Religiosität gewesen sein, s<strong>on</strong>dern umgekehrt, die Genesis des Dogmas ist nur verständlich aus<br />

dem Vollzug der christlichen Lebenserfahrung.” See also Dil<strong>the</strong>y, Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften,<br />

258 (“So war die Entwicklung dieses Gehaltes im Dogma zugleich seine Veräußerlichung”),<br />

274 (“hat sich die Entwicklung der Formeln, welche die religiöse Erfahrung in einer<br />

Verknüpfung v<strong>on</strong> Vorstellungen abgrenzen und gegen <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ere Formeln innerhalb derselben <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

wie gegen <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ere <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g>en rechtfertigen sollten, nicht folgerecht aus der im Christentum<br />

gegebenen Selbstgewißheit innerer Erfahrung vollzogen”). Th e <strong>the</strong>sis of <strong>the</strong> unhappy c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong><br />

of Christianity with Greek philosophy was far from being unknown <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous generati<strong>on</strong><br />

of liberal <strong>the</strong>ology, e.g., <strong>to</strong> Ritschl; <strong>on</strong> this point, see Wolfhart Pannenberg, Problemgeschichte der<br />

neueren evangelischen Th eologie in Deutschl<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>. V<strong>on</strong> Schleiermacher bis zu Barth und Tillich (Göttingen:<br />

V<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>enhoeck & Ruprecht, 1997), 123. As <strong>to</strong> Overbeck, Heidegger refers <strong>to</strong> him in <strong>the</strong><br />

Preface <strong>to</strong> his Phenomenology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Th eology.<br />

89) See GA 59: 91.<br />

90) GA 60: 310: “Scharf zu trennen: das Problem der Th eologie und das der Religiosität.” And<br />

he adds signifi cantly:“Die Th eologie hat bis jetzt keine originäre <strong>the</strong>oretische Grundhaltung der<br />

Ursprünglichkeit des Gegenst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>es entsprechend gefunden.”


128 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

of faith,” 91 where faith is c<strong>on</strong>ceived of in terms of a specifi c way of being<br />

of Dasein (GA 9: 52) encompassing, as it were, <strong>the</strong> whole domain or horiz<strong>on</strong><br />

within which al<strong>on</strong>e <strong>the</strong> specifi c “objects” of faith, for example, God, can<br />

appear. Faith is thus prior <strong>to</strong> God, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> it would be a serious mistake or a vulgarizati<strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>to</strong> defi ne <strong>the</strong>ology naively as <strong>the</strong> “science of God” or <strong>the</strong> “speculative<br />

knowledge of God” (GA 9: 59)—wherein God would be an object of <strong>the</strong><br />

respective science in <strong>the</strong> same way as <strong>the</strong> animals are <strong>the</strong> objects of zoology<br />

(ibid.). Th eology originates from faith (GA 9: 55), has its roots in faith, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> in<br />

general makes sense <strong>on</strong>ly for faith (GA 9: 61), i.e, <strong>the</strong> believer. In this sense,<br />

faith anticipates <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> founds <strong>the</strong>ology (GA 9: 60f.). Th e suffi cient motives of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ology as well as its justifi cat<strong>on</strong> may lie <strong>on</strong>ly in faith itself (GA 9: 54, 55),<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>y lie in faith’s attempt at a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual interpretati<strong>on</strong> of itself (“begriffl<br />

iche Auslegung” [GA 9: 54], “begriffl iche Selbstinterpretati<strong>on</strong> der gläubigen<br />

Existenz” [GA 9: 56]). Th e believing comportment (Gläubigkeit) can never<br />

originate from <strong>the</strong>ology, but <strong>on</strong>ly through faith itself (GA 9: 56). Now, <strong>the</strong><br />

task of <strong>the</strong>ology is <strong>to</strong> fi nd a c<strong>on</strong>ceptuality adequate <strong>to</strong> faith (GA 9: 60), <strong>the</strong><br />

believing comportment <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> existence, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tribute <strong>to</strong> developing <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ning this attitude (GA 9: 55, 61)—a formulati<strong>on</strong> which c<strong>on</strong>fi rms<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> justifi es <strong>to</strong> a great extent Gadamer’s interpetive recollecti<strong>on</strong> of Heidegger’s<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>ology in <strong>the</strong> postwar years. 92<br />

Th e relati<strong>on</strong> between faith <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>ology, within <strong>the</strong> encompassing phenomen<strong>on</strong><br />

of religi<strong>on</strong>, bears c<strong>on</strong>spicuous similarities <strong>to</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> may be seen as a<br />

development or a radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of, Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s linking Erlebnis with Ausdruck 93<br />

or with Heidegger’s subsequent characterizati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong> between underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> interpretati<strong>on</strong> in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong> (§32). Th is may be summed up<br />

as follows: <strong>on</strong>ly what is unders<strong>to</strong>od can be interpreted; underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing c<strong>on</strong>stitutes<br />

<strong>the</strong> fundament <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> starting point of every interpretati<strong>on</strong>. In this<br />

sense, faith is <strong>the</strong> fundament of <strong>the</strong>ology, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong> latter is but a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<br />

91) GA 9: 55. Th e following numbers in paren<strong>the</strong>ses in <strong>the</strong> body of <strong>the</strong> text refer <strong>to</strong> this editi<strong>on</strong><br />

(GA 9: 45–77). For a detailed rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of this lecture, see Joseph J. Kockelmans, “Heidegger<br />

<strong>on</strong> Th eology,” in Th inking About <strong>Being</strong>: Aspects of Heidegger’s Th ought, ed. R. W. Shahan <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

J. N. Mohanty (Norman, Oklahoma: University of Oklahoma Press, 1984), 85–108.<br />

92) See also Annemarie Gethmann-Siefert, Das Verhältnis v<strong>on</strong> Philosophie und Th eologie im Denken<br />

Martin Heideggers (Freiburg: Alber, 1974), 36: “religi<strong>on</strong> requires a way of treatment adequate<br />

<strong>to</strong> its logos.”<br />

93) See, for example, Dil<strong>the</strong>y, Der Ausbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften,<br />

132, 206. Dil<strong>the</strong>y employs here even <strong>the</strong> characteristic expressi<strong>on</strong> Erlebnisausdruck. His additi<strong>on</strong><br />

of Verstehen <strong>to</strong> this structure is for us here irrelevant.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 129<br />

articulati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> former, erecting itself up<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> remaining forever grounded<br />

in it. Th eological knowledge must arise from faith <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> return <strong>to</strong> it.<br />

Th e way <strong>the</strong>ology relates itself <strong>to</strong> faith exhibits structural analogies <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

way philosophy relates itself <strong>to</strong> facticity. Both <strong>the</strong>ology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> philosophy off er<br />

a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual elaborati<strong>on</strong> of something previously enacted or lived (a sort of<br />

having-been) <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>, in doing so, are at <strong>the</strong> same time meant <strong>to</strong> refer back <strong>to</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

reinforce what <strong>the</strong>y grow out of—faith or factical life. Given this strict correlati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

it is no w<strong>on</strong>der that we fi nd in Heidegger’s texts similarities between<br />

his characterizati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong>ology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> philosophy. Th e well-known defi niti<strong>on</strong><br />

of philosophy in <strong>Being</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>Time</strong> goes like this: “Philosophie ist universale<br />

phänomenologische On<strong>to</strong>logie, ausgehend v<strong>on</strong> der Hermeneutik des Daseins,<br />

die . . . das Ende des Leitfadens dort festgemacht hat, woraus es entspringt und<br />

wohin es zurückschlägt” (SZ 38); while Phenomenology <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Th eology characterizes<br />

<strong>the</strong>ology as follows: “Alle <strong>the</strong>ologische Erkenntnis ist . . . auf den Glauben<br />

selbst gegründet, sie entspringt aus ihm und springt in ihn zurück” (GA 9: 61).<br />

“[W]oraus es entspringt und wohin es zurückschlägt” <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> “. . . entspringt aus ihm<br />

und springt in ihn zurück” show obvious parallels both c<strong>on</strong>ceptually <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> with<br />

regard <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> matter itself. Both are Dasein’s ways of being, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> both move<br />

in a hermeneutic circle. Th ey are a re-enacting accompaniment of what <strong>the</strong>y<br />

grow out of—factical life or rebirth by faith—, helping <strong>to</strong> interpretively illuminate,<br />

that is, appropriate <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> re-appropriate, that from which <strong>the</strong>y originate.<br />

And <strong>the</strong> b<strong>on</strong>d that links philosophy’s <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>the</strong>ology’s self-interpretati<strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r is a hermeneutical <strong>on</strong>e: an always already having unders<strong>to</strong>od of what<br />

<strong>on</strong>e has become as a starting point for a subsequent interpretati<strong>on</strong>. 94<br />

It may be of interest <strong>to</strong> note that in <strong>the</strong> Phenomenology of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Religi<strong>on</strong></str<strong>on</strong>g> course we<br />

fi nd an important anticipati<strong>on</strong> of this defi niti<strong>on</strong>: “Bisher waren die Philosophen<br />

bemüht, gerade die faktische Lebenserfahrung als selbstverständliche Nebensächlichkeit<br />

abzutun, obwohl doch aus ihr gerade das Philosophieren entspringt,<br />

und in einer . . . Umkehr wieder in sie zurückspringt.” 95 Th is is an important early<br />

anticipati<strong>on</strong> of what Heidegger will come <strong>to</strong> develop in 1927, which I take <strong>to</strong> be<br />

a fur<strong>the</strong>r illustrati<strong>on</strong> of my <strong>the</strong>sis that Heidegger’s underst<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>ing of philosophy<br />

is permeated by, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> emerges as a radicalizati<strong>on</strong> of, <strong>the</strong>ological motives (whereby<br />

<strong>the</strong>ology becomes re-interpreted <strong>to</strong>o). <str<strong>on</strong>g>Philosophy</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s self-interpretati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

Heidegger provides may be regarded as relying for its emergence <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> selfinterpretati<strong>on</strong><br />

of <strong>the</strong>ological comportment as a model. Heidegger, as it were,<br />

94) See GA 60: 336: “Die Analyse, d.h. die Hermeneutik, arbeitet im his<strong>to</strong>rischen Ich.” “[I]n<br />

allem ist die spezifi sche Sinnbestimm<strong>the</strong>it herauszuhören.”<br />

95) GA 60: 15 (italics added); see ibid., 8, 124.


130 I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131<br />

transposes <strong>the</strong> self-interpretati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ological comportment <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> level<br />

of philosophy in a specifi cally modifi ed <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> formalized form. 96<br />

References<br />

Texts of Heidegger’s Gesamtausgabe (Frankfurt a.M.: Vit<strong>to</strong>rio Klostermann)<br />

are referenced in <strong>the</strong> above essay according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> volume number. Listed<br />

below are <strong>the</strong> respective titles, edi<strong>to</strong>rs, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> dates of publicati<strong>on</strong> for each referenced<br />

volume number.<br />

GA 1 Frühe Schriften. Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 1978.<br />

GA 9 Wegmarken. Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 2004.<br />

GA 17 Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung. Edited by F.-W.<br />

v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 2006.<br />

GA 20 Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriff s. Edited by Petra Jaeger.<br />

1994.<br />

GA 21 Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit. Edited by Walter Biemel. 1995.<br />

GA 24 Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie. Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong><br />

Herrmann. 1997.<br />

GA 29/30 Die Grundbegriff e der Metaphysik. Welt—Endlichkeit—Einsamkeit.<br />

Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 2004.<br />

GA 32 Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Edited by Ingtraud Görl<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>.<br />

1997.<br />

GA 39 Hölderlins Hymnen ‘Germanien’ und ‘Der Rhein.’ Edited by Susanne<br />

Ziegler. 1999.<br />

GA 45 Grundfragen der Philosophie. Ausgewählte ‘Probleme’ der ‘Logik.’<br />

Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 1992.<br />

GA 56/57 Zur Bestimmung der Philosophie. Edited by Bernd Heimbüchel.<br />

1999.<br />

GA 58 Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie. Edited by Hans-Helmuth<br />

G<str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g>er. 1992.<br />

96) Revelati<strong>on</strong> is, Heidegger says, not just a matter of delivering or collecting positive knowledge<br />

about real occurrences, past or future, but it is a matter of participati<strong>on</strong>, that is, taking part, in <strong>the</strong><br />

c<strong>on</strong>tent of what <strong>the</strong> revelati<strong>on</strong> is about. In this participati<strong>on</strong>, that is, faith, Dasein gets placed in<br />

fr<strong>on</strong>t of God, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> his existence, aff ected by <strong>the</strong> revelati<strong>on</strong>, becomes aware of itself, reveals itself <strong>to</strong><br />

itself, in a state of forgottenness of God (“Gottvergessenheit” [GA 9: 53]). In precisely <strong>the</strong> same<br />

manner Dasein, eff ecting <strong>the</strong> passage from <strong>the</strong> inau<strong>the</strong>ntic <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntic, gains awareness of<br />

itself for <strong>the</strong> fi rst time <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> it does so in terms of existing always already in an inau<strong>the</strong>ntic way.


I. M. Fehér / Research in Phenomenology 39 (2009) 99–131 131<br />

GA 59 Phänomenologie der Anschauung und des Ausdrucks. Th eorie der philosophischen<br />

Begriff sbildung. Edited by Claudius Strube. 2007.<br />

GA 60 Phänomenologie des religiösen Lebens. Edited by Matthias Jung,<br />

Th omas Regehly, <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g> Claudius Strube. 1995.<br />

GA 61 Phänomenologische Interpretati<strong>on</strong>en zu Aris<strong>to</strong>teles. Einführung in<br />

die phänomenologische Forschung. Edited by Walter Bröcker <str<strong>on</strong>g>and</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

Käte Bröcker-Oltmanns. 1994.<br />

GA 63 On<strong>to</strong>logie. Hermeneutik der Faktizität. Edited by Käte Bröcker-<br />

Oltmanns. 1995.<br />

GA 64 Der Begriff der Zeit. Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 2004.<br />

GA 65 Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis). Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong><br />

Herrmann. 2003.<br />

GA 66 Besinnung. Edited by F.-W. v<strong>on</strong> Herrmann. 1997.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!